The Federal Reserve Board eagle logo links to home page

Skip to: [Printable Version (PDF)] [Bibliography] [Footnotes]
Finance and Economics Discussion Series: 2008-19 Screen Reader version

Happiness Maintenance and Asset Prices

Antonio Falato*
This draft: January, 2008

Keywords: State-dependent utility, affect and decisionmaking, equity premium puzzle

Abstract:

This paper constructs a simple dynamic asset pricing model which incorporates recent evidence on the influence of immediate emotions on risk preferences. Investors derive direct utility from both consumption and financial wealth and, consistent with the happiness maintenance feature documented by Isen (1999) and others, become more cautious toward their wealth in good times. Mild pro-cyclical changes in risk aversion over wealth cause large pro-cyclical fluctuations in the current price-dividend ratio which, due to general equilibrium restrictions, translate into counter-cyclical variation in the current consumption-wealth ratio and, in turn, in expected future returns. With a realistic consumption growth process and reasonable preference parameters, the model generates a sizable equity premium, a low and stable risk-free rate, volatile and predictable stock returns, and price-dividend and Sharpe ratios in line with the data.

JEL Codes: D81, D91, E44, G12.


I. Introduction

Empirical research in finance has extensively documented the failure of traditional asset pricing models to account for the historically observed level, volatility, and cyclical behavior of asset returns. The last decade has witnessed some progress in bringing theory closer to the data (see, for example, Campbell and Cochrane (1999) and Bansal and Yaron (2004)). Nevertheless, the identification of the fundamental sources of aggregate risk that drive expected returns remains an open challenge.

This paper proposes a new analytical framework based on the link between immediate emotions and risk preferences. The starting point of my analysis is the well replicated finding that individuals who feel good are more risk averse than individuals who feel neutral (see Isen (1999) for a thorough review of the evidence). This finding is consistent with the notion that individuals have a preference for happiness maintenance: accepting a gamble when happy puts their happiness, in addition to any tangible stake, at risk.

I embed happiness maintenance preferences into an otherwise standard equilibrium asset pricing model along the lines of Lucas (1978) and Mehra and Prescott (1985). In my model, investors derive direct utility from both consumption and financial wealth. The current state of the economy changes their attitude toward wealth gambles, which I refer to as "hedonic" risk aversion: in good times investors prefer not to "push their luck" - i.e., they become more conservative toward their portfolio risk.

I show, both analytically and numerically, that happiness maintenance goes a long way toward accounting for stock market facts. With a realistic consumption growth process and reasonable risk aversion and time preference parameters, my model delivers a sizable equity premium, a low and stable risk-free rate, volatile and predictable stock returns, and price-dividend and Sharpe ratios in line with the data.

What is the economic mechanism behind these results? In essence, it is a "leverage effect" that makes equity riskier for an investor with happiness maintenance preferences. To see this point, consider that changes in hedonic risk aversion induce changes in investors' views about how valuable wealth is relative to consumption. This is the reason why the level of the wealth to consumption ratio, rather than its volatility, emerges as an extra source of risk: even if wealth were to stay constant, investors in my model would consider equity risky, due to the need to hedge swings in their hedonic risk aversion. Thus, changes in hedonic risk aversion increase the standard deviation of investors' intertemporal marginal rate of substitution. The increase in perceived risk leads investors to require a higher return on risky assets for any given level of consumption and wealth risk.

It is worth stressing the two main features that distinguish happiness maintenance from previous models. First, in contrast to previous models that add a second term to the utility function, such as financial or housing wealth (e.g. Bakshi and Chen (1996), Piazzesi et al (2005), Barberis et al (2001)), happiness maintenance generates a large equity premium without the need for financial wealth to be too volatile. This is the case since the leverage effect depends on the level, rather than the volatility, of the wealth-consumption ratio. Second, in contrast with habit persistence models that rely on high and strongly counter-cyclical effective risk aversion (e.g. Campbell and Cochrane (1999), but also Barberis, Huang and Santos (2001) who need strongly counter-cyclical loss aversion), low and mildly pro-cyclical hedonic risk aversion is sufficient for the leverage effect to be operative. Thus, my results highlight that counter-cyclical risk aversion is not a necessary condition for equilibrium asset pricing models to replicate stock market facts.

Happiness maintenance differs from the standard consumption-based approach of Campbell and Cochrane (1999) also in terms of the predictions of the model. In the consumption-based model, stock return volatility is generated through changes in risk aversion that are driven by consumption. Thus, in contrast with the data, stock returns and consumption are strongly correlated. My wealth-based framework weakens the correlation between returns and consumption since stock return volatility is driven not only by consumption, but also by wealth. Thus, the multi-factor structure of my model distinguishes it from standard consumption-based approaches.

My study makes the following four additional contributions to the literature. First, I identify a fundamentally different source of equity risk, which is complementary to standard consumption and wealth volatility (see Kocherlakota (1996) for a comprehensive survey).

Second, my model contributes to the literature on predictability (for a survey see Cochrane (2000)). In fact, in my model the consumption-wealth ratio predicts expected returns. Lettau and Ludvigson (2001) provide empirical evidence of a common component in expected returns and the consumption-wealth ratio. With happiness maintenance preferences, such common component emerges in equilibrium, as the level of the consumption-wealth ratio directly affects the riskiness of stocks. Thus, my model offers a general equilibrium perspective over the earlier empirical findings.

Third, my work contributes to the wealth-based asset pricing literature (e.g. Bakshi and Chen (1996), Epstein and Zin (1989, 1991)) by addressing the Campbell (1993) critique. This class of models identifies the volatility of wealth as a risk factor. However, these models do not generate volatile wealth with low risk aversion since they imply a constant price/dividend ratio. In other words, the fact that consumption is smooth and wealth is volatile is itself a puzzle that must be explained. My full-fledged general equilibrium setting directly address this issue: even with low risk aversion, the leverage effect allows me to generate endogenously a realistic volatility of wealth.

Finally, my paper contributes to the growing literature on emotions and investor behavior (e.g. Lo and Repin (2001), Mehra and Sah (2001); see Loewenstein (2000) for a survey). Saunders (1993) and Kamstra, Kramer and Levi (2000) document an empirical relationship between weather or length of the day and asset returns, which they interpret as evidence of an impact of moods on asset prices. Lo and Repin (2001) offer direct evidence of an emotional reaction of investors to risk by documenting significant correlation between changes in stock market traders' cardiovascular variables and market volatility. Mehra and Sah (2001) formally explore the role of small fluctuations in investors' preferences within a non-rational expectations framework. To the best of my knowledge, my paper represents the first comprehensive equilibrium treatment of emotions and asset prices.

Outline of the paper

The first section develops a formal representation of happiness-maintenance preferences which are then embedded into an otherwise standard equilibrium asset pricing model. The second section characterizes equilibrium returns in an economy populated by investors with happiness-maintenance preferences. The results of a simple calibration exercise are in the third section, which investigates the quantitative implications of happiness maintenance. The fourth section concludes. Algebraic derivations and proofs are in Appendix A. Tables and Figures are in Appendix B.

II. A wealth-based capital asset pricing model

In this section I develop a formal representation of investors' happiness maintenance preferences and embed into an otherwise standard dynamic equilibrium asset pricing model.

II.1 Setup

Mine is a standard "endowment economy" (Lucas (1978), Mehra and Prescott (1985)) populated by a large number of infinitely-lived investors, who are identical with respect to their preferences, endowments and expectations and face a standard consumption/saving problem. Given these assumptions, it is customary to aggregate investors into a representative agent. There is one consumption good. The only source of income is a large number of identical and infinitely-lived fruit trees, each in fixed supply. Without loss of generality, the supply of trees is normalized to unity and it is assumed that there exists one tree per individual, so that the amount of fruit produced by a tree in period  t, denoted  y_{t}, represents the output or dividend per capita. Fruits are non-storable, cannot be used to increase the number of trees and can only be used for consumption. They are uncertain and evolve according to  y_{t+1}=x_{t+1}y_{t}, where  x_{t+1}\in\{\lambda_{1}, ... ,  \lambda_{n}\} is the growth rate of output which follows a given stationary stochastic process to be detailed on later. Each tree has a single perfectly divisible equity claim outstanding on it. In each period there is a spot market for the consumption good and a financial market in which equity shares are exchanged at a price  p_{t}. Consequently, the gross rate of return on equity holdings from period  t to period  t+1 is defined as  R_{t+1}% =\frac{p_{t+1}+y_{t+1}}{p_{t}}. A one-period risk-free asset in zero net supply at a price  p_{t}^{f} completes the description of the "technology" side of the economy. It pays a gross interest rate  R_{t}^{f}=\frac{1}{p_{t}^{f}}.

Investor preferences

Investors derive utility from a composite good,  g_{t}, which includes both current (per-capita) consumption,  c_{t}, and current (per-capita) financial wealth,  w_{t}. They rank random sequences of the composite good according to

\displaystyle U_{0}=E_{0}\sum_{t=0}^{\infty}\beta^{t}u\left( g_{t}\right) ,\qquad u\left( g_{t}\right) =\frac{g_{t}^{1-\alpha}}{1-\alpha}%
where  \beta\in\left( 0,1\right) is the subjective discount factor,  E_{0}\left[ \cdot\right] is the expectations operator conditional on the information available at time zero, and  \alpha>0 has the conventional interpretation of the parameter of relative risk aversion. The composite good,  g_{t}, represents my main departure from standard assumptions and the remaining part of this section details its connection with happiness maintenance.

In contrast to standard models, investors' financial wealth,  w_{t}, enters their preferences directly over and above the indirect utility of the consumption services it provides ,1 that is

\displaystyle g_{t}=g\left( c_{t},w_{t};\theta_{t}\right) =c_{t}^{1-\theta_{t}}% w_{t}^{\theta_{t}}%
The parameter  \theta_{t}\in\left[ 0,1\right] controls the (relative) demand for financial happiness: values of  \theta_{t} close to the lower (upper) bound of the  \left[ 0,1\right] interval correspond to a low (high) demand for happiness relative to consumption. The level of financial wealth measures financial performance. It is introduced directly into the utility function to capture the wide range of non-consumption related pleasures associated with ownership of financial assets, such as, for example, power and social status, but also sense of security and control from having resources. Total financial wealth,  w_{t}, is defined by the value of the beginning-of-period asset holding,  s_{t}, and dividends,  y_{t}, at the current prices,  p_{t}, i.e.  w_{t}=\left( p_{t}+y_{t}\right) s_{t}.

Affect-maintenance preferences are modelled as an instance of state-dependent preferences by postulating a state-dependent demand for financial happiness. Appendix A gives a standard set of axioms and a representation theorem for these preferences. To facilitate intuition on the connection between  \theta_{t} and happiness maintenance, it is useful to rewrite the utility function as

\displaystyle U_{0}=E_{0}\sum_{t=0}^{\infty}\beta^{t}\frac{c_{t}^{1-\alpha}}{1-\alpha }\left( \frac{w_{t}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t}} % (1)

Investors' expected utility has a decision component, which depends on current consumption, and a hedonic component, which depends on the performance of their portfolios. Financial income relative to consumption is assumed to provide a first approximation indicator of this performance and, hence, a direct source of happiness with respect to financial wealth. Thus, the term  \left( \frac{w_{t}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t}} formalizes the intuition that investors' utility depends on their experienced happiness. If  \theta_{t}=\theta\neq0, the model reduced to a standard wealth-based setup (Bakshi and Chen (1996), Epstein and Zin (1989)). When  \theta_{t}=\theta=0, the model reduces to the standard consumption-based asset pricing framework. Thus, these extreme parametrizations provide useful benchmarks to gauge the marginal contribution of happiness maintenance.

One important implication of % latex2html id marker 5175 $ \left( \ref{interpreta1}\right) $ is that a mean preserving spread of financial wealth (relative to consumption) directly reduces investors' utility. If financial wealth is a source of happiness, the desire to maintain happiness should determine the size of the reduction of investors' utility. In fact, while investors' relative risk aversion over  g_{t} gambles,  \alpha, is constant, investors' hedonic risk aversion,  a_{t}, that is their risk aversion2 over portfolio risk, is a simple function of their demand for financial happiness. By definition,3 hedonic risk aversion is

\displaystyle a_{t}=\left( \alpha-1\right) \theta_{t}+1\in\left( 1,\alpha\right)
As far as  \alpha>1 - a restriction maintained throughout the paper and necessary to satisfy the standard transversality condition for the infinite horizon problem4 -  a_{t} is increasing in  \theta_{t}. In this sense, for any given  \alpha,  \theta_{t} determines by how much a mean preserving spread of financial wealth (relative to consumption) reduces investors' utility. I use the following simple specification:
\displaystyle \theta_{t} \displaystyle =\theta\overline{x}_{t}\left( n\right) ,\qquad\theta >0 (2)
\displaystyle \overline{x}_{t}\left( n\right) \displaystyle =\frac{1}{n+1}\sum_{\tau=0}^{n}% x_{t-\tau}=\frac{1}{n+1}\sum_{\tau=0}^{n}\frac{y_{t-\tau}}{y_{t-\tau-1}% }    

where  \overline{x}_{t}\left( n\right) is the average of the recent  n states of the economy and  \theta_{t} is an increasing function of the state of the economy. Notice that, for any given  \alpha,  a_{t} is higher in good times, i.e., risk aversion is pro-cyclical: in good times investors become more risk averse toward financial wealth (relative to consumption) in an attempt to maintain their happiness.

The parameter  n controls how far back in the past investors look to determine whether times are good or bad. When  n=0, definition % latex2html id marker 5235 $ \left( \ref{happy}\right) $ simplifies to  \theta_{t}=\theta x_{t}=\theta\frac {y_{t}}{y_{t-1}}. In this case good times are measured simply by the current state of the economy. If  n\geq1, a mean of the recent past states of the economy measures investors' hedonic risk aversion. This is broadly consistent with the psychological evidence on incidental emotions, which documents the existence of a durability or projection effect (see Loewenstein et al. (2001) for a survey): investors' current moods are affected by the recent economic trend. An alternative interpretation is that investors' views about current times are formed by extrapolating from the recent past.

In summary, the choices of an investor with affect-dependent preferences are fully characterized by the triple  \left( \beta,\alpha,\theta_{t}\right) , i.e., respectively, by his subjective rate of time preference,  \beta, his relative risk aversion,  \alpha, and his relative demand for financial happiness,  \theta_{t}. Variables  \left( s_{t},y_{t},\theta_{t}\right) are sufficient relative to the entire history of shocks up to, and including, time  t for predicting the subsequent evolution of the economy. They thus constitute legitimate state variables for the model.

Further discussion of assumptions

Happiness maintenance is a well replicated finding (for a detailed overview of the experimental psychology findings see Isen (1999) and Appendix A). While earlier studies indicate a tendency toward conservatism for individuals in a good mood, the study by Isen et al. (1988) is most relevant since it focuses directly on the notion of risk aversion typically employed in economics and finance. The study examined the slope of the utility associated with various outcomes, as a function of positive affect induced by means of a small bag of candy. Participants were asked to make choices between pairs of simple 50-50 gambles in such a way that a set of indifference points could be found and individual utility functions constructed. The average utility curves were computed for the two groups and people in whom positive affect had been induced displayed steeper utility function than controls.

Finally, notice that in my specification  u\left( \cdot\right) is iso-elastic, which insures stationarity of returns and is broadly consistent with an established stylized fact of the relationship between individual emotional well-being and aggregate economic conditions (see Easterlin (2000) and Frey and Stutzer (2002) for recent surveys): there is no clear cut trend, positive or negative, in self-reported subjective well-being over periods of 20 to 30 years in rich countries. In particular, in the United States between 1946 and 1991, per capita real income has risen by a factor of 2.5, but happiness, on average, remained constant.

II.2 The consumption-saving problem

Given the asset price function,  p_{t}=p\left( s_{t},y_{t},\theta_{t}\right) , initial asset holdings,  s_{0}, the initial state of the economy,  y_{0}, and initial affective state,  \theta_{0}, the problem of the "stand-in" investor is to choose a sequence of plans for consumption,  c_{t}, and end-of-period asset holdings,  s_{t+1}, that maximizes her present discounted expected utility subject to the budget constraint. Formally, the investor chooses consumption and asset holdings that solve the following

  \displaystyle \max_{\left\{ c_{t},s_{t+1}\right\} }E\sum_{t=0}^{\infty}\beta ^{t}u(g\left( c_{t},w_{t};\theta_{t}\right) ) (3)
\displaystyle c_{t}+p_{t}s_{t+1} \displaystyle =\left( p_{t}+y_{t}\right) s_{t}=w_{t}    
\displaystyle c_{t} \displaystyle >0, \displaystyle s_{t+1}\in\left( 0,1\right] , and \displaystyle s_{0}% ,y_{0} \displaystyle \theta_{0} given    

where  u\left( g_{t}\right) is defined in % latex2html id marker 5279 $ \left( \ref{interpreta1}% \right) $ and  \theta_{t} is defined in % latex2html id marker 5283 $ \left( \ref{happy}\right) .$

This problem admits a recursive formulation which, through standard perturbation arguments, delivers5 the following Euler equation:

  \displaystyle u_{c}\left( g\left( c_{t},w_{t};\theta_{t}\right) \right) p_{t}    
  \displaystyle =\beta E_{t}\left[ \left( u_{c}\left( g\left( c_{t+1},w_{t+1}% ;\theta_{t+1}\right) \right) +u_{w}\left( g\left( c_{t+1},w_{t+1}% ;\theta_{t+1}\right) \right) \right) \left( p_{t+1}+y_{t+1}\right) \right]% (4)

where  u_{c} and  u_{w} denote the partial derivative of the utility function with respect to consumption and wealth, respectively. The basic intuition is common to a broad class of wealth-based asset pricing models: by reducing consumption by  p_{t} units in the first period, the agent can purchase one unit of the asset, thereby raising consumption by  s_{t+1} units in the second period. Importantly, this decision entails a portfolio adjustment which has a direct effect on investor's utility, as indicated by the second term on the right-hand side of equation % latex2html id marker 5297 $ \left( \ref{eulero}% \right) $. The distinctive feature of happiness maintenance is that the extent to which portfolio adjustments change investors' utility depends on hedonic risk aversion,  a_{t+1}. Moreover, investors fully anticipate changes in their hedonic risk aversion and, consequently, can fully hedge this extra source of uncertainty.

The Euler equation is derived using only the preferences and budget constraint of the investor. Before exploiting the restrictions imposed by equilibrium on asset returns, it is useful to consider the consequences of the individual budget constraint and preferences for asset returns. The risk-free interest rate is given by

\displaystyle R_{f}=\frac{1}{\beta E\left[ \left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{-\alpha }\left( \frac{w_{t+1}/c_{t+1}}{w_{t}/c_{t}}\right) ^{1-a_{t+1}}% k_{t+1}\left( \frac{w_{t}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{a_{t}-a_{t+1}}\right] } % (5)

where  a_{t}=\left( \alpha-1\right) \theta_{t}+1 is the hedonic risk aversion,  k_{t+1}\equiv\left( \frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t}}\right) \left( 1+\frac{\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t+1}}\frac{c_{t+1}}{w_{t+1}}\right) , and  \theta_{t} and  \theta_{t+1} are defined in % latex2html id marker 5311 $ \left( \ref{happy}% \right) $. How does happiness maintenance help to match a relatively low rate of returns on riskless securities? To see the intuition, consider the following two parametric choices. First, when  \theta_{t}=\theta_{t+1}% =\theta=0 the risk-free rate reduces to the standard consumption-based asset pricing framework of Mehra and Prescott (1985):
\displaystyle R_{f}=\frac{1}{\beta E\left[ \left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{-\alpha }\right] }% (6)

Under % latex2html id marker 5317 $ \left( \ref{RfMP}\right) ,$ it is difficult to generate a low risk-free rate since the very feature that helps to explain the equity premium - i.e., a high curvature  \alpha of utility over consumption - also leads to a strong desire to smooth consumption intertemporally, generating high interest rates. As standard in wealth-based models (e.g. Bakshi and Chen (1996)) and in models that introduce a second variable into the utility function (e.g. Piazzesi et al (2005)), happiness maintenance adds a second factor, wealth growth, to the determination of returns. To see this, consider the case when  \theta_{t}=\theta_{t+1}=\theta\neq0:
\displaystyle R_{f}=\frac{1}{\beta E\left[ \left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( 1-\theta\right) -1}\left( \frac{w_{t+1}}{w_{t}% }\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta}\tilde{k}_{t+1}\right] }%
where  \tilde{k}_{t+1}\equiv\left( 1+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}\frac{c_{t+1}% }{w_{t+1}}\right) . Adding a second risk factor could in principle help, since it allows to explain the equity premium with a lower curvature  \alpha of utility, thus contributing to a lower risk-free rate relative to Mehra and Prescott (1985) . However, it is well known that adding wealth as a second factor does not really help to resolve the puzzles, since high risk aversion is still needed to generate enough volatility of wealth in equilibrium (Campbell (1993)).

Happiness maintenance adds an extra source of volatility,  a_{t}, which is fundamentally different from standard consumption and wealth uncertainty. To see this, consider the last term in the denominator of % latex2html id marker 5333 $ \left( \ref{rf0}% \right) ,\left( \frac{w_{t}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{a_{t}-a_{t+1}}:$ since hedonic risk aversion changes, investors' marginal utility varies even if there is no consumption or wealth uncertainty. Importantly, large consumption or wealth swings are not needed to generate enough volatility since happiness maintenance introduces a "leverage effect," which depends on the level, rather than the growth rate, of the wealth/consumption ratio. It is this leverage effect that gives to mild variation in hedonic risk aversion potency for asset pricing.

The intuition for how the leverage effect works is straightforward: changes in hedonic risk aversion make  a_{t+1}-a_{t} stochastically negative or positive. Thus, in contrast to other models with state-dependent preferences such as Campbell and Cochrane (1999), even small changes in hedonic risk aversion can generate substantial volatility as the wealth to consumption ratio operates as either a discount or a compound factor depending on whether  a_{t+1}-a_{t} is negative or positive. This effect magnifies the contribution of consumption and wealth volatility to the standard deviation of investors' intertemporal marginal rate of substitution, thus increasing investors' perceived risk. As a result, investors seeking safety in the risk-free asset bid its price up, which lowers the risk-free return.

In summary, since the main mechanism in my model operates through changes in hedonic risk aversion, I do not need high curvature of the utility function to match the equity premium. This is the way my model contributes to the resolution of the risk-free rate puzzle. Moreover, since I only need small changes in hedonic risk aversion, I can maintain a relatively stable interest rate.

The leverage effect implied by happiness maintenance depresses the price of risky assets. In fact, the expected return on equity is

\displaystyle 1=\beta E\left[ \left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{-\alpha}\left( \frac{w_{t+1}/c_{t+1}}{w_{t}/c_{t}}\right) ^{1-a_{t+1}}k_{t+1}\left( \frac{w_{t}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{a_{t}-a_{t+1}}R_{t+1}\right] ,% (7)

and the implied (conditional) expected premium demanded by the investor to hold her wealth in equities,  E\Pi=ER_{t+1}-R_{f}, is
\displaystyle R_{f}cov\left( -\left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{-\alpha}\left( \frac{w_{t+1}/c_{t+1}}{w_{t}/c_{t}}\right) ^{1-a_{t+1}}k_{t+1}\left( \frac{w_{t}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{a_{t}-a_{t+1}},R_{t+1}\right)% (8)

The expected premium, as stated in % latex2html id marker 5345 $ \left( \ref{prem}\right) $, depends upon the familiar covariation of the intertemporal marginal rate of substitution and the return on equities. In line with the discussion of the risk-free rate, the leverage effect that operates under happiness maintenance represents a novel source of risk as the covariance in % latex2html id marker 5347 $ \left( \ref{prem}\right) $ is non zero even with constant consumption and wealth growth. In other words, an investor with affect-maintenance preferences would still require a premium to hold equities even if she were to face no consumption or wealth uncertainty.

To see the intuition for this last point, consider the term  \left( \frac{w_{t}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{a_{t}-a_{t+1}} in % latex2html id marker 5351 $ \left( \ref{prem}\right) :$ equity is riskier for an investor with happiness maintenance preferences since she fears that changes in hedonic risk aversion will change her views about how valuable wealth is relative to consumption. This is the reason why the level of the wealth to consumption ratio matters for risk: as  a_{t+1}-a_{t} stochastically changes from negative to positive, the wealth to consumption ratio induces lower discounting. Thus, happiness maintenance introduces a leverage effect that increases the standard deviation of investors' intertemporal marginal rate of substitution. The increase in perceived risk leads investors to require a higher return on risky assets for any given level of consumption and wealth risk.

It is worth stressing three important features that distinguish happiness maintenance from previous resolutions of the equity premium puzzle. First, the wealth to consumption ratio is bounded even in a growing economy, since the budget constraint of the investor holds. Thus, in contrast to previous consumption-based models with state-dependent preferences (e.g. Danthine et al. (2003) and Gordon and St-Amour (2000)), happiness maintenance preferences preserve stationarity of returns. Second, in contrast to previous models that add a second term to the utility function, such as financial or housing wealth (e.g. Bakshi and Chen (1996) and Piazzesi et al (2005)), happiness maintenance does not need financial wealth to be too volatile to be able to generate large enough premiums. This is the case since the leverage effect increases the impact of wealth volatility on the volatility of the pricing kernel. Finally, in contrast with most habit persistence models that rely on a strongly counter-cyclical risk aversion,6 as the next section will make clearer, I only need mild variation in hedonic risk aversion for the leverage effect to be operative. Thus, happiness maintenance does not need to make interest rates counterfactually volatile.

III. Aggregate asset pricing implications
of happiness maintenance

Can affect maintenance provide a satisfactory analytical account of the main stylized facts of financial markets? To address this question, I characterize equilibrium asset prices and returns in an economy populated by investors with happiness maintenance preferences. I then study the quantitative properties of the model vis-a-vis the historical record of US stock returns in the post-war period.

III.1 Equilibrium characterization of returns

Given the fixed supplies of goods and assets, it is trivial to determine quantity choices in a competitive equilibrium: all fruits are consumed during the period in which they are produced, i.e.,  c_{t}=y_{t}, and the representative investor holds all her wealth in the risky asset,  s_{t}=s_{t+1}=1. Since consumer-investors are assumed to have identical preferences, per-capita consumption of the representative investor equals aggregate consumption, which then equals aggregate output.

Equilibrium is characterized by the asset price function that supports this allocation, that is by the function  p_{t}=p\left( y_{t},s_{t},\theta _{t}\right) that solves % latex2html id marker 5365 $ \left( \ref{eulero}\right) .$ Loosely speaking, the optimality conditions that correspond to the solution of the investor's problem defined in % latex2html id marker 5367 $ \left( \ref{problema}\right) $ and the requirement of market clearing in the aggregate provide the equilibrium pricing equation for the risk-free and risky assets. For the probability structure specified in the next section, Appendix A contains a proof of the existence of equilibrium. The following proposition offers a characterization of equilibrium asset returns.

Proposition 1   Given the preferences in % latex2html id marker 5374 $ \left( \ref{problema}\right) $ the equilibrium risk-free interest rate and equilibrium expected return on equity satisfy, respectively,
\displaystyle R_{f}=\frac{1}{\beta E\left[ x_{t+1}^{-\alpha}\left( \frac{f_{t+1}+1}% {f_{t}+1}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t}}k\left( f_{t+1}\right) \left( f_{t+1}+1\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( \theta_{t+1}-\theta_{t}\right) }\right] }% (9)

and
\displaystyle 1=\beta E\left[ x_{t+1}^{-\alpha}\left( \frac{f_{t+1}+1}{f_{t}+1}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t}}k\left( f_{t+1}\right) \left( f_{t+1}+1\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( \theta_{t+1}-\theta _{t}\right) }R_{t+1}\right]% (10)

where  k\left( f_{t+1}\right) =\left( \frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t}% }\right) \left( 1+\frac{\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t+1}}\left( f_{t+1}% +1\right) ^{-1}\right) ,  \theta_{t} and  \theta_{t+1} are defined in % latex2html id marker 5386 $ \left( \ref{happy}\right) \ $and  f_{t}=\frac{p_{t}}{y_{t}}.
Proof. see Appendix A.  \qedsymbol

An important qualification of my results transpires from this characterization of equilibrium returns. Since all the investor's wealth is financial, in equilibrium there is a tight mapping between the properties of the wealth to consumption ratio and the price-dividend ratio. However, recent empirical work by Menzly, Santos and Veronesi (2004) and Lustig, Van Nieuwerburgh and Verdelhan (2007) has shown that these two ratios behave quite differently in the presence of human capital, government transfers or, in general, non financial income. While beyond the scope of this paper, integrating non-financial wealth into the model is an important question for future research.

A Note on Aggregation

The equilibrium pricing equations in % latex2html id marker 5394 $ \left( \ref{rf1}\right) $ and % latex2html id marker 5396 $ \left( \ref{re1}\right) $ are derived under the assumption that investors are homogeneous. This is certainly a strong assumption. Investors may be heterogeneous along a variety of dimensions, which raises the question of aggregation.

Since in my economy financial markets are competitive and complete, and investors' preferences satisfy the axioms of expected utility (see Appendix A for a formal proof), existence of a representative (single agent) economy with the same aggregate consumption series as the heterogeneous agent economy and the same asset price functions is guaranteed by construction (Prescott and Mehra (1980)). However, it is well known that these properties do not guarantee strict-aggregation, i.e. that the representative agent can be constructed independent of the underlying heterogeneous agent economy's initial wealth distribution.

The question of whether happiness maintenance admits strict-aggregation is important but beyond the scope of this paper. However, there are reasons to believe that the intuition of my model is likely to go through under several types of investor heterogeneity. The results should generalize to any particular form of heterogeneity such that aggregate hedonic risk aversion still varies with the aggregate state of the economy. Another form of heterogeneity that does aggregate is when investors have different wealth levels, but identical wealth to income ratios, a case that can be modelled by having several cohorts of investors, each with a continuum of equally wealthy investors.

While this is speculative, there are good reasons to believe that my intuition will survive more extreme forms of heterogeneity, such as, for example, when investors differ in their hedonic risk aversion,  a. Even if  a varies across investors, as far as each individual investor has pro-cyclical hedonic risk aversion there is no reason to believe that this property will be lost in the aggregate.

III.2 Quantitative assessment

In order to gain insight into the quantitative effect of affect maintenance on aggregate asset returns, I compute numerical solutions to the problem of the investor defined in % latex2html id marker 5403 $ \left( \ref{problema}\right) $ for various parameter choices and use these solutions to compute the associated time averaged risk-free rate, market rate, and risk premium as implied by equations % latex2html id marker 5405 $ \left( \ref{rf1}\right) $ and % latex2html id marker 5407 $ \left( \ref{re1}\right) $. The choice of specific values for the behavioral parameters and the aggregate growth rate of output,  x_{t}, is crucial for the empirical evaluation of the model.

Calibration of the "technology" side of the model is standard. I consider two alternative stochastic processes for the aggregate output growth,  x_{t}. In the first case, as in Mehra and Prescott (1985),  x_{t} follows a Markov chain and the number of states  n is limited to two  \left( \lambda_{1},\lambda_{2}\right) ,with transition probabilities given by  \Pi and defined as

\displaystyle \lambda_{1} \displaystyle =1+\mu+\delta,\qquad\lambda_{2}=1+\mu-\delta (11)
\displaystyle \Pi \displaystyle =\left[ \begin{array}[c]{cc}% \pi & 1-\pi\\ 1-\pi & \pi \end{array} \right]    

The parameters  \mu,  \delta and  \pi are chosen to match respectively the mean, standard deviation and first order autocorrelation of aggregate consumption growth in the US economy between 1889 and 1985. The values required are  \mu=0.018,  \delta=0.036,  \pi=0.43.

In the second case, aggregate output growth follows an iid lognormal process (as in Campbell and Cochrane (1999)), i.e.

\displaystyle \log x_{t+1}=\mu+\delta\epsilon_{t+1}% (12)

Investor preference parameters,  \left( \beta,\alpha,\theta_{t}\right) , are chosen based on evidence from field studies and the consensus view in the previous literature. It is customary to choose a time preference coefficient,  \beta, close to and lower than one. A negative rate of time preference has been shown to be effective in "solving" the risk-free rate puzzle, but introspection provides a strong argument in support of a positive rate of time preference. Consequently, I choose the  \beta lower than one that optimizes the performance of the model with respect to the risk-free rate.

The literature after Mehra and Prescott (1985) deems reasonable risk aversion coefficients within the  \left( 0,10\right) interval. Field studies support this choice, since an  \alpha beyond 10 would imply rejections of consumption (and wealth) bets that most subjects in experiments do not turn down. I choose risk aversion close to the lower bound of the interval  \left( 0,10\right) to explore the full extent to which happiness maintenance can account for stock market facts without resorting to high risk aversion. Given that  \alpha>1 is needed to satisfy the transversality condition of the infinite horizon problem, I take  \alpha to be equal to 3.

Given the simple specification of  \theta_{t} in % latex2html id marker 5457 $ \left( \ref{happy}\right) ,$ I need to determine reasonable ranges of two parameters,  \theta and  n. Recall that, for the composite good  g_{t} to be well defined,  \theta_{t} has to lie at every point of time within the  \left[ 0,1\right] interval. This suggests a first restriction for  \theta\in\left[ 0,\frac{1}% {\overline{x}_{t}\left( n\right) }\right] . Neither psychological experiments nor introspection provide guidance on how to further restrict  \theta. I take a pragmatic stand and consider the interval  \left[ 0,0.5\right] . This is a conservative choice, since it constrains the demand for happiness to be lower than that for consumption, and hedonic risk aversion to be always lower than  \alpha and less volatile than the underlying state of the economy. In fact, with  \alpha=3 hedonic risk aversion is  a_{t}=2\theta_{t}+1=2\theta\overline{x}_{t}\left( n\right) +1, and its standard deviation is  \sigma\left( a_{t}\right) =\sigma\left( \theta _{t}\right) =2\theta\sigma\left( \overline{x}_{t}\left( n\right) \right) \leq2\theta\delta. Thus,  \theta_{t}\in\left[ 0,0.5\right] implies  a_{t}\in\left( 1,2\right) and  \sigma\left( a_{t}\right) \in\left( 0,0.036\right) . Finally, since the model is calibrated on yearly frequency, I constrain  n within the  \left[ 0,5\right] interval so as to roughly span the average length of a business cycle. This restriction implies that investors span at most an entire cycle in their assessment of recent economic conditions. In summary, my preference parameter values are  \beta\in\left( 0.97,0.99\right) ,  \alpha=3, and  \theta_{t}\in\left[ 0,0.5\right] .

Two features of my calibration are worth emphasizing. First, my parametrization implies low and mildly volatile hedonic risk aversion, which is consistent with the emphasis of happiness maintenance experiments on mild everyday emotions. Second, my two-parameter specification of  \theta_{t} is relatively parsimonious in that it allows for fewer free parameters than previous wealth-based models (see, for example, Barberis et al. (2001)). Finally, in contrast to Campbell and Cochrane (1999), I am not forcing the  \theta_{t} process to match the stochastic properties of returns.

Computing returns

Expected returns cannot be solved for in closed form and need to be computed using numerical methods. As in Mehra and Prescott (1985), the definition of returns can be used to rewrite equation % latex2html id marker 5504 $ \left( \ref{re1}\right) $ in terms of the price-dividend ratio. Since the pricing kernel does not depend on the level of consumption, I do not expect asset prices to depend on consumption levels either. Thus, it is natural to assume that the price of equities is  p^{e}(c_{t},\lambda_{i},\theta_{i})  =f_{i}c_{t}, where  f_{i}=\frac {p^{e}(c_{t},\lambda_{i},\theta_{i})}{c_{t}} is a price-dividend ratio function related to  \lambda_{i}, the growth rate of output, both directly and through the dependence of  \theta_{t} on  \lambda_{i}. Under probability structure % latex2html id marker 5518 $ \left( \ref{probabilita1}\right) ,$ the Euler equation defines a system of (nonlinear) first-order difference equations in unknown price-dividend ratios (see Appendix A for details) . Using these price relationships, I can compute the conditional and unconditional expectation of asset returns.7

The number of first-order difference equations and price-dividend ratios defined by the Euler and the methods adopted to actually solve these equations depend on the value of  n. In particular, when  n=0,  \theta_{i}% =\theta\lambda_{i}, the price-dividend ratio,  f_{i}=\frac{p^{e}% (c_{t},\lambda_{i})}{c_{t}}, depends only on the growth rate of output, and the Euler equation defines a system of two equations in two unknowns which can be solved as in Mehra and Prescott (1985). When  n\in\left[ 1,5\right] , the Euler in general defines more than two equations. This is the case since  \theta_{i} depends on past realizations of aggregate dividend growth, which induces time-variation in expected returns and makes the price-dividend ratio,  f_{i}=\frac{p^{e}(c_{t},\lambda_{i},\theta_{i})}{c_{t}}, depend effectively on two states,  \lambda_{i} and  \theta_{i}. Since the traditional solution methodology is not applicable to this case, I employ standard simulation methods . In particular, I employ a simple parametrized expectation algorithm (see Marcet and Marshall (2002) for a detailed description of the algorithm) and then compute summary statistics by simulating the solved system to generate a long times series of 50,000 data points.8

III.2.a The risk-free rate, the equity premium, and the volatility puzzles

In the US, the mean excess return of equities over relatively riskless securities such as bonds - i.e., the equity premium - has been historically about six percent, with riskless securities paying an average return of about one percent. Riskless securities have displayed significantly lower volatility of returns than equities, with a difference of about ten percentage points. Consequently, the so called Sharpe ratio, which is defined as the mean of the equity premium divided by its standard deviation, has been in the neighborhood of .32. The first three columns of Table 1 show that these facts hold robustly across different time periods. The first column is especially important since it is an updated version of the sample used in Mehra and Prescott (1985), which constitutes the classical benchmark to evaluate the empirical performance of asset pricing models.

To facilitate comparison, the fourth column of Table 2 reports the predictions of the traditional consumption-based asset pricing model (to which my model reduces if I shut down demand for happiness by setting  \theta_{t}% =\theta_{t+1}=0) under the parameters chosen and Markov consumption growth. This offers a quantitative counterpart to my discussion of asset pricing puzzles in the previous section: the predicted premium is one order of magnitude smaller than the actual one (the "equity premium puzzle" of Mehra and Prescott (1985)), and the risk free rate is too high (the "risk-free rate puzzle" of Weil (1989)). Moreover, both returns display excessively low volatilities and the implied Sharpe ratio is too low.

Adding wealth as a second term in the utility function provides limited help toward the resolution of the puzzles. In fact, contrary to the partial equilibrium results of Bakshi and Chen (1996), the predictions of a basic wealth-based model - to which the present model reduces when happiness maintenance is shut down by setting  \theta_{t}=\theta_{t+1}=\theta\neq0 - are virtually indistinguishable from those of the consumption-based model. In fact, general equilibrium implies that the restrictions imposed by the budget constraint on the relationship between wealth and consumption need to be taken into account. In this case, the fifth column of Table 2 shows that introducing a demand for wealth increases prices and lowers both returns, but has virtually no effect on the premium and on the volatility of returns. This is consistent with Campbell (1993): if risk aversion is kept relatively low as in my calibration, standard wealth-based models fail to generate volatile wealth since the implied price/dividend ratio is essentially constant.

The fourth and fifth columns of Table 1 contrast these results with the predictions of happiness maintenance. With relatively low (on average about 1.5) and mildly volatile (standard deviation of about 0.01) hedonic risk aversion, the implied premium is more than ten times bigger than either the wealth-based or the consumption-based benchmarks. Moreover, stock market volatility ceases to be a puzzle. A low level of risk aversion and a reasonable rate of time preference need not be inconsistent with the basic facts of asset markets, i.e. a fairly stable and low average return on riskless securities and a sizable and fairly volatile premium of equities over bonds. While these results obtain regardless of the stochastic process chosen for consumption growth, with iid consumption growth the mean and volatility of the price-dividend ratio are closer to the data.

Given that the implications of the model are analogous under iid and Markov consumption growth, I present the next results under the Markovian assumption. The results are not meaningfully different under iid consumption growth.9

Volatility bounds and the market price of risk.

To fully explore the quantitative effects of happiness maintenance on returns, it is useful to consider Hansen and Jagannathan (1991)'s statement of the equity premium puzzle, according to which the largest possible Sharpe ratio is given by the conditional standard deviation of the log stochastic discount factor. More formally,

\displaystyle \left\vert \frac{E\left( R^{i}\right) -R^{f}}{\sigma\left( R^{i}\right) }\right\vert \leq\frac{\sigma_{t}\left( m_{t+1}\right) }{E_{t}m_{t+1}}%
where  \frac{E\left( R^{i}\right) -R^{f}}{\sigma\left( R^{i}\right) } is the Sharpe ratio,  \frac{\sigma_{t}\left( m_{t+1}\right) }{E_{t}m_{t+1}} is the market price of risk and  m_{t+1} is the investors' intertemporal marginal rate of substitution. In this formulation, the " equity premium puzzle" lies in the fact that standard models make the conditional standard deviation of the pricing kernel too small.

I have argued in the previous section that happiness maintenance increases the volatility of the pricing kernel through a leverage effect,  \left( \frac{w_{t}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{a_{t}-a_{t+1}}. Panels B-D of Figure 1 show that, even with low and moderately procyclical hedonic risk aversion, the leverage effect is strong enough to bring the equilibrium pricing kernel well within Hansen-Jagannathan bounds. This is in sharp contrast to Panel A, which shows that, even with a risk aversion of 10, the market prices of risk implied by power utility falls short from satisfying the bounds.

Inspecting the mechanism.

In contrast to the habit-persistence preferences of Campbell and Cochrane (1999), happiness maintenance matches the equity premium without high implied risk aversion. In fact, risk aversion in my model is constant and equal to  \alpha. Moreover, while the elasticity of intertemporal substitution is different from  \frac{1}{\alpha} and is a complicated function of the other parameters of the model, in my benchmark calibration it is equal to 0.4, a value which is well within the range commonly assumed in the literature.10

The comparative dynamics of the coefficient of relative risk aversion,  \alpha, and the rate of time preference,  \beta, under happiness maintenance are standard and, thus, omitted for brevity .Not surprisingly, the value of hedonic risk aversion is key for the empirical performance of the model. Table 3 illustrates this point by experimenting with several different combinations of values for  \alpha and  \theta that, however, imply the same mean and volatility of hedonic risk aversion as in my benchmark calibration. The message is that, as far as hedonic risk aversion preserves the features of my baseline calibration, the model can match the Sharpe ratio for a wide range of combinations of values of  \theta and  \alpha. Even with risk aversion as low as 2, the model can deliver a premium in line with the data.

III.2.b Cyclicality and the correlation puzzle

The first column of Table 4 reports stylized facts about the price-dividend ratio over the business cycle: the price-dividend ratio is procyclical and displays positive auto-correlation. In contrast to standard consumption-based models that imply a counter-cyclical price-dividend ratio, the cyclicality and autocorrelations of the price-dividend ratio implied by my model are in line with the data. In the next section, I discuss the intuition for this result in the context of predictability.

Before moving on, though, it is worth contrasting another dimension along which happiness maintenance improves the fit with the data. It is well known that standard consumption-based models imply a correlation between stock returns and consumption growth equal to one, which is much higher than in the data. This is the "correlation puzzle" of Cochrane and Hansen (1992). Happiness maintenance alleviates the puzzle since it predicts a correlation well below 1. To understand this, note that in my model stock returns are made up of two standard components, news about consumption and wealth, and a novel component, changes in hedonic risk aversion. Although changes in hedonic risk aversion are ultimately caused by changes in consumption, the rich multi-factor structure of the model lowers the correlation between returns and consumption.

III.2.c Long-horizon predictability and volatility

Can pro-cyclical changes in hedonic risk aversion reproduce the observed patterns of predictability of asset returns? To develop intuition about this question, it is helpful to start by considering the implications of happiness maintenance for the volatility of equity prices. To this end, Table 5 presents the results of regressions of long-horizon log stock price changes on long-horizon log consumption changes. The first column shows that in the data these regressions yield coefficients invariably greater than one, and as high as 1.61 at a 20-year horizon. Barsky and DeLong (1993) characterize this finding as the "excess volatility" of stock prices. In contrast to traditional consumption-based asset pricing models, happiness maintenance generates stock prices that are more volatile than underlying consumption fundamentals (as evidenced by the coefficients in the third and forth columns which are consistently greater than one).

To see how the model generates prices that are more volatile than the underlying dividends, suppose that there is a positive consumption innovation this period. This shock increases current hedonic risk aversion,  a_{t}, which is pro-cyclical. However, as indicated by the term  \left( \frac{w_{t}% }{c_{t}}\right) ^{a_{t}-a_{t+1}} in % latex2html id marker 5593 $ \left( \ref{re0}\right) ,\footnote{Or, equivalently, by the term $\left( f_{t+1}+1\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( \theta_{t+1}-\theta_{t}\right) }$\ in $\left( \ref{re1}\right) .$}$ what matters for a forward-looking investor is the anticipated change in hedonic risk aversion,  a_t+1-a_t. Thus, a positive consumption innovation makes the future look relatively brighter, i.e. it actually implies a lower expected change in hedonic risk aversion. This increases the value of wealth relative to consumption for the investor (recall from % latex2html id marker 5597 $ \left( \ref{interpreta1}\right) $ that  \theta, and, thus,  a, control the relative demand for wealth). As a result, as it is clear from % latex2html id marker 5603 $ \left( \ref{re0}\right) ,$the investor discounts the future dividend stream at a lower rate, giving stock prices an extra jolt upward. A similar mechanism works for a negative shock, which generates low current hedonic risk aversion and pushes prices lower. The ultimate effect is that prices are more volatile than consumption growth.

This mechanism is also underlying long horizon predictability: since the investor's hedonic risk aversion varies over time depending on the state of the economy, expected returns on the risky asset also vary. To understand this in more detail, suppose once again that there is a positive shock to consumption, which increases the investor's current hedonic risk aversion. This makes wealth relatively more valuable with respect to consumption, since the investor expect a lower change in hedonic risk aversion. The higher demand for wealth pushes the stock price still higher, leading to a higher price-dividend ratio. At the same time, higher demand for wealth implies that subsequent stock returns will be lower on average, since the investor demands a lower premium to bear equity risk. Price-dividend ratios are therefore inversely related to future returns. Notice that, although my model generates predictability through state-dependent preference as Campbell and Cochrane (1999), the economic mechanism is distinct from theirs. One advantage of my leverage effect is its non-linearity in risk aversion changes - i.e. small switches in risk aversion are sufficient for the term  \left( \frac{w_{t}% }{c_{t}}\right) ^{a_{t}-a_{t+1}} to operate as either a discount or a compound factor. Thus, I only need mild, rather than strong, cyclicality of risk aversion.

The results reported in Table 6 confirm this intuition about predictability. In particular, I report the slope coefficients,  \beta_{k}, and  R_{k}^{2} obtained from running the following regression of cumulative log returns over a k-year horizon on lagged price-dividend ratio:

\displaystyle r_{t+1}+r_{t+2}+...+r_{t+k}=\alpha_{k}+\beta_{k}\left( p_{t}-y_{t}\right) +\epsilon_{k,t}%
where  r_{t+k} is log return and  k=1,2,3,5 and 10. For ease of comparison, the corresponding values in the data and in the standard consumption-based model are reported in the first and second columns of Table 6, respectively. The stylized patterns documented by Campbell and Shiller (1988) are well replicated by the model: the coefficients are negative; they start low and then increase. Finally, the  R^{2} increases with the return horizon.

III.3 Robustness checks

The results in Table 7 show that the model is robust to alternative specifications of the happiness demand process which preserve the pro-cyclicality of hedonic risk aversion. In particular, the third column of Table 7 shows that replacing specification % latex2html id marker 5622 $ \left( \ref{happy}% \right) $ with a different pro-cyclical process for  \theta_{t} produces returns that are virtually indistinguishable from the benchmark calibration.

Finally, the second column of Table 7 contrasts the implication of happiness maintenance (reported, for ease of comparison, in the first column) with those of a model where hedonic risk aversion is counter-cyclical. I report summary statistics of asset returns when the happiness demand process  \theta_{t} is perfectly negatively correlated with consumption growth. This departure from the baseline model makes the premium shrink to about a quarter of its benchmark value, mostly due to the fact that the risk-free rate is four times as high.

IV. Conclusion

Drawing on ingredients from outside the usual domain of finance and economics can help to understand several otherwise puzzling features of financial markets. In particular, I use an equilibrium model simple to the extreme and show that mild everyday feelings have rich implications for aggregate asset returns. Happiness maintenance, a well documented feature of the immediate emotional perception of risk, increases the risk associated with equity, thus contributing to resolve some of the most prominent documented asset pricing puzzles. Further, it provides a novel perspective over a broad set of important stylized features of financial markets, such as, the predictability of asset returns and the volatility of asset prices at long horizons.

An important feature of my model is that it does not depart from conventional asset pricing wisdom along any dimensions other than investors' preferences. Moreover, my two-parameter specification of happiness maintenance preferences is relatively parsimonious with respect to other wealth-based models. Overall, my results strongly suggest that pro-cyclical risk aversion provides a potentially useful construct to understand stock market facts.

Bibliography

Bakshi, Gurdip S., and Zhiwu Chen, 1996.
"The Spirit of Capitalism and Stock-Market Prices," American Economic Review, 86(1), pp.133-57.
Bansal, Ravi and Amir, Yaron, 2004.
"Risks for the Long Run: A Potential Resolution of Asset Pricing Puzzles," Journal of Finance, 59,pp.1481-1509.
Barberis, Nicholas, Ming Huang, and Tano Santos, 2001.
"Prospect Theory and Asset Prices," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 116(1), pp.1-53.
Barsky, Robert, and J. Brad De Long, 1993.
"Why Does the Stock Market Fluctuate?" Quarterly Journal of Economics, 107, pp.291-311.
Campbell, John Y., 1993.
"Intertemporal Asset Pricing Without Consumption Data," American Economic Review, 83, pp.487-512.
Campbell, John Y., 1999.
"Asset Prices, Consumption, and the Business Cycle," in John Taylor and Michael Woodford, eds.: Handbook of Macroeconomics, Vol. 1, North-Holland, Amsterdam.
Campbell, John Y., and John H. Cochrane, 1999.
" By Force of Habit: A Consumption-Based Explanation of Aggregate Stock Market Behavior," Journal of Political Economy, 107, pp. 205-251.
Campbell, John Y., and Robert J. Shiller, 1988.
"The Dividend-Price Ratio and Expectations of Future Dividends and Discount Factors," Review of Financial Studies, 1, pp.195-228.
Carroll, Christopher D., 2000.
"Why Do the Rich Save So Much?," in Does Atlas Shrug? The Economic Consequences of Taxing the Rich ,ed. by J. B. Slemrod, Harvard University Press.
Cochrane, John H., 2000.
Asset Pricing, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
Cochrane, John H., and Lars Peter Hansen, 1992.
"Asset Pricing Lessons for Macroeconomics," in O. J. Blanchard and S. Fischer, eds.: NBER Macroeconomics Annual 1992, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Constantinides, George, 1990.
"Habit Formation: A Resolution of the Equity Premium Puzzle," Journal of Political Economy, 98, pp.519-43.
Easterlin, Richard A., 2000.
"The Worldwide Standard of Living Since 1800," Journal of Economic Perspectives, 14(1), pp.7-26.
Epstein, Lawrence, and Stanley Zin, 1989.
" Substitution, Risk Aversion, and the Temporal Behavior of Consumption and Asset Returns: A Theoretical Framework," Econometrica, 57, pp.937-69.
Falato, Antonio, 2008.
"Happiness Maintenance and Asset Prices," working paper, Federal Reserve Board.
Frey, Bruno S., and Alois Stutzer, 2002.
"What Can Economists Learn from Happiness Research?," Journal of Economic Literature, 40, pp.402-35.
Danthine, Jean-Pierre, John B., Donaldson, Chrisos, Giannikos, and Hany, Guirguis, 2003.
"On the Consequences of State Dependent Preferences for the Pricing of Financial Assets," CEPR Discussion Paper #3697.
Gordon, Stephen, and Pascal St-Amour, 2000.
"A preference regime model of bull and bear markets," American Economic Review, 90(4), pp.1019-33.
Hansen, Lars P., and Ravi Jagannathan, 1991.
" Restrictions on Intertemporal Marginal Rates of Substitution Implied by Asset Returns," Journal of Political Economy, 99, pp.225-62.
Isen, Alice M., 1999.
"Positive Affect and Decision Making," in Lewis M. and J. M. Haviland Eds., Handbook of Emotions, New York, The Guilford Press.
Isen, Alice M., Thomas E. Nygren, and Gregory F. Ashby, 1988.
"Influence of Positive Affect on the Subjective Utility of Gains and Losses: It is Just not Worth the Risk," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 55, pp.710-17.
Isen, Alice M., and Robert Patrick, 1983.
"The Effect of Positive Feelings on Risk-Taking: When the Chips are Down," Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 31, pp.194-202.
Kamstra, Mark J., Lisa A. Kramer, and Maurice D. Levi, 2000.
"Losing Sleep at the Market: The Daylight-Savings Anomaly," American Economic Review, 90, pp. 1005-11.
Kocherlakota, Narayana, 1990.
"On the 'Discount' Factor in Growth Economies," Journal of Monetary Economics, 25, pp.43-47.
Kocherlakota, Narayana, 1996.
"The Equity Premium: It's Still a Puzzle," Journal of Economic Literature, 34, pp.42-71.
Lettau, Martin and Sydney Ludvigson, 2001.
" Consumption, Aggregate Wealth, and Expected Stock Returns," Journal of Finance, 56(3), pp. 815-850.
Lo, Andrew W., and Dmitry V. Repin, 2001.
"The Psychophysiology of Real-Time Financial Risk Processing," NBER Working Paper No.8508.
Loewenstein, George F., 2000.
"Emotions in Economic Theory and Economic Behavior," American Economic Review, 90, pp.426-32.
Loewenstein, George F., Elke U. Weber, Christopher K. Hsee, and Edward S. Welch, 2001.
"Risk as Feelings," Psychological Bulletin, 127(2), pp.112-37.
Lucas, Robert E. Jr., 1978.
"Asset Pricing in an Exchange Economy," Econometrica, 46, pp.1429-45.
Lustig, Hanno, Stijn Van Nieuwerburgh, and Adrien Verdelhan, 2007,
"The Wealth-Consumption Ratio: A Litmus Test for Consumption-based Asset Pricing Models," mimeo, New York University
Marcet, Albert and David Marshall, 2002.
" Convergence of Approximate Model Solutions to Rational Expectations Equilibria Using the Method of Parameterized Expectations," forthcoming, Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control.
Mehra, Rajnish and Prescott Edward, 1985.
"The Equity Premium: a Puzzle," Journal of Monetary Economics, 15, pp.145-61.
Mehra, Rajnish, and Raaj Sah, 2002.
"Mood Fluctuations, Projection Bias, and Volatility of Equity Prices," Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 26(5), pp.869-87.
Melino, Angelo, and Alan X., Yang, 2003.
"State Dependent Preferences can explain the Equity Premium Puzzle," Review of Economic Dynamics, 6(4), pp.806-30.
Menzly, Lior, Tano Santos and Pietro Veronesi, 2004.
"Understanding predictability," Journal of Political Economy, 112, pp. 1-47.
Milnor J., 1997.
Topology from the Differentiable Viewpoint, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2nd edition.
Piazzesi, Monica, Martin Schneider, and Selale Tuzel, 2005.
"Housing, Consumption, and Asset PRicing," forthcoming, Journal of FInancial Economics.
Pigou, Arthur C., 1947.
"Economic Progress in a Stable Environment," Economica, 14, pp.180-88.
Prescott, Edward C., and Rajnish Mehra., 1980.
" Recursive Competitive Equilibrium: The Case of Homogeneous Households." Econometrica, 48, pp. 1365 -1379.
Weil, Philippe, 1989.
"The Equity Premium Puzzle and the Riskfree Rate Puzzle," Journal of Monetary Economics, 24, pp.401-21.
Zhou, Heng-fu, 1994.
"The Spirit of Capitalism and Long-Run Growth," European Journal of Political Economy, 10, pp.279-93.
Zin, Stanley E., 2001.
"Are Behavioral Asset-Pricing Models Structural?" Journal of Monetary Economics, 49, pp.215-28.


Appendix A: Evidence of Happiness Maintenance, Derivations, and Proofs

Happiness maintenance is a well replicated finding. For example, Isen and Patrick (1983) conducted an experiment to study the influence of positive affect on choices under uncertainty. Participants, a large sample of college students, were randomly assigned to two groups: positive affect was induced only in participants in one group by receipt of a small gift, a McDonald's gift certificate worth $.50. Subjects were given ten poker chips and told that these chips represented their credit for participating in the study. Risk preferences were measured in terms of the amount of chips actually bet by the two groups of participants in a game of roulette. They found that individuals in a positive mood bet significantly less than controls on gambles with a meaningful probability of losing (about 20% chance of winning). In particular, individuals in a neutral state bet on average about six times as many chips as individuals in a positive mood11. Isen and Geva (1987) used the level of the probability of winning before accepting a bet of fixed amount and found again that, when a meaningful amount was at stake, namely their whole endowment of chips, individuals in a positive mood, in contrast to those in a control group, set a level for the probability of winning as a cutoff point for accepting a given gamble on average about 30% higher than controls. Isen et al. (1984) documented that individuals in whom a positive mood had been induced by receipt of a small gift expressed greater preference in a lottery choice for a $1 ticket rather than a $10 ticket relative to a control group. Nygren et al. (1996) provided stronger support for an influence of affect on risk taking: they asked participants in whom positive affect had been induced, as well as no manipulation controls, to make actual betting decisions in twelve different three-outcome gambles. The mean bet value of affect condition participants was found to be consistently lower of about 30% than controls, regardless of the riskiness of the gambles, i.e. the ratio of the probability of winning and loosing or of the amounts.

While these early results indicated a tendency toward conservatism in risk preferences, Fong and McCabe (1999) replicate their essence within a very careful experimental setup that through the adoption of auction theoretic techniques (see Kagel (1995)) enables them to avoid potential difficulties with the studies mentioned so far, especially associated with the possible role of uncontrolled variables, the lack of monetary incentives and the lack of mechanism to ensure that truthful revelation of private values of the lottery was a dominant strategy. They endowed their subjects with lottery tickets and let them bid for the tickets in both a sealed-bid and an English auction. Subjects could earn up to $10 in each lottery or as little as zero in each. They found that average exit price is significantly lower for subjects whose mood had been improved by a minor manipulation, indicated a higher risk aversion in affect subjects.

The perspective suggested by these findings is well described by the idiom: don't push your luck. It is worth contrasting it with the findings of illusion of control or "gambling with the house money" of Thaler and Johnson (1990), which motivate the work of Barberis et al. (2001). As suggested in Arkes et al. (1988), the presence of a meaningful loss might be the crucial determinant of the discrepancy between the findings of the two classes of experiments. In one experiment, where a meaningful loss was nonexistent, affect participants exhibited relatively more risk-prone behavior compared to controls. In a second experiment dealing with insurance buying behavior where participants were forced to focus on potential loss, positive affect participants displayed a greater risk aversion than did controls. Nygren et al. (1996) further illustrates this point: positive affect participants significantly overestimated the probability of winning while participants in the control group did not, in accord with the findings of studies such as Johnson and Tversky (1983). Nevertheless, in actual gambling situations, affect condition participants were much less likely to gamble than were controls.

Axioms and representation theorems for state-dependent utility

Technically, the specification chosen for the affect-dependent utility belongs to the wider class of state-dependent utility functions. The structure of the preferences underlying state-dependent utility functions is relatively well understood. Karni (1985) and more recently Dreze and Rustichini (2001) present a thorough analysis of alternative axiomatizations. I follow Myerson (1991) and give a list of axioms and a representation theorem for state-dependent preferences of the type informally illustrated in the text.

Notation

For any finite set  Z, let  \Delta\left( Z\right) denote the set of probability distributions over  Z. That is, define:

\displaystyle \Delta\left( Z\right) =\left\{ q:Z\rightarrow R\mid\sum_{y\in Z}q\left( y\right) =1\text{ and }q\left( z\right) \geq0,\forall z\in Z\right\}

Let  \ X denote the set of possible prizes that the decision maker could ultimately get,  \Omega denote the set of possible states of the world, and assume both  \ X and  \Omega are finite. Define a lottery to be any function  f that specifies a nonnegative real number  f\left( x\mid t\right) , for every prize  x in  \ X and every state  t in  \Omega, such that  \sum_{x\in X}f\left( x\mid t\right) =1 for every  t in  \Omega.

Let  L denote the set of all such lotteries. That is,

\displaystyle L=\left\{ f:\Omega\rightarrow\Delta\left( X\right) \right\}

For any state  t in  \Omega and any lottery  f in  L,  f\left( \cdot\mid t\right) denotes the probability distribution over  \ X designated by  f in state  t. That is,

\displaystyle f\left( \cdot\mid t\right) =\left\{ f\left( x\mid t\right) \right\} _{x\in X}\in\Delta\left( X\right)

Let  \Xi denote the set of all events,  S, so that

\displaystyle \Xi=\left\{ S\mid S\subseteq\Omega\text{ and }S\neq\emptyset\right\}

For any two lotteries  f and  g in  L and any event  S in  \Xi, I write  f\succsim_{S}g if and only if (iff) the lottery  f would be at least as desirable as  g, in the opinion of the decision-maker, if he knew that the true state of the world was in the set  S. In other words,  f\succsim_{S}g iff the decision-maker would be willing to choose the lottery  f when he has to choose between  f and  g and he knows only that the event  S has occurred. Given the relation  \succsim_{S},I can define

\displaystyle f \displaystyle \succ_{S}g iff \displaystyle f\succsim_{S}g and \displaystyle g\succsim_{S}f    
\displaystyle f \displaystyle \sim_{S}g iff \displaystyle f\succsim_{S}g and \displaystyle g\nsim_{S}f    

where  f\succ_{S}g and  f\sim_{S}g have the customary meanings of (conditional) indifference and (conditional) strict preference. Naturally,  \succsim_{\Omega},  \succ_{\Omega} and  \sim_{\Omega}correspond to the familiar  \succsim,\succ and  \sim, that is when no conditioning event is considered, I refer to prior preferences.

For any number  \alpha such that  0\leq\alpha\leq1, and for any two lotteries  f and  g in  L,  \alpha f+\left( 1-\alpha\right) g denotes the lottery in  L such that

\displaystyle \left( \alpha f+\left( 1-\alpha\right) g\right) \left( x\mid t\right) =\alpha f\left( x\mid t\right) +\left( 1-\alpha\right) g\left( x\mid t\right)
for all  x\in X and  t\in\Omega.

Finally, a conditional-probability function on  \Omega is any function  p:\Xi\rightarrow\Delta\left( \Omega\right) that specifies nonnegative conditional probabilities  p\left( t\mid S\right) for every state  t in  \Omega and every event  S, such that  p\left( t\mid S\right) =0 if  t\notin S and  \sum_{r\in S}p\left( r\mid S\right) =1.

Axioms

The axioms are to hold for all lotteries  e,f,g and  h in  L, for all events  S and  T in  \Xi, and for all numbers  \alpha and  \beta between 0 and 1:

Axiom 2 (Completeness)    f\succsim_{S}g or  g\succsim_{S}f.
Axiom 3 (Transitivity)   If  f\succsim_{S}g and  g\succsim_{S}h, then  f\succsim_{S}h.
Axiom 4 (Relevance)   If  f\left( \cdot\mid t\right) =g\left( \cdot\mid t\right) ,  \forall t\in S, then  f\sim_{S}g.
Axiom 5 (Monotonicity)   If  f\succ_{S}h and  0\leq\beta<\alpha\leq1, then  \alpha f+\left( 1-\alpha\right) h\succ_{S}\beta f+\left( 1-\beta\right) h.
Axiom 6 (Continuity)   If  f\succsim_{S}g and  g\succsim_{S}h, then there exists some number  \gamma such that  0\leq\gamma\leq1 and  g\sim_{S}\gamma f+\left( 1-\gamma\right) h.
Axiom 7 ((Strict) objective substitution)   If  e\left( \succ_{S}\right) \succsim_{S}f and  g\succsim_{S}h and  0\left( <\right) \leq\alpha\leq1, then  \alpha e+\left( 1-\alpha\right) g\left( \succ_{S}\right) \succsim_{S}\alpha f+\left( 1-\alpha\right) h.
Axiom 8 ((Strict) subjective substitution)   If  f\left( \succ_{S}\right) \succsim _{S}g and  f\succsim_{T}g and  S\cap T=\varnothing, then  f\left( \succ_{S\cup T}\right) \succsim_{S\cup T}g.
Axiom 9 (Interest)   For every state  t in  \Omega, there exist prizes  y and  z in  \ X such that  \left[ y\right] \succ_{\left\{ t\right\} }\left[ x\right] , where  \left[ \cdot\right] denotes the lottery that always gives the prize for sure.

A representation theorem

A utility function can be any function from  X\times\Omega into the real numbers,  \Re. A utility function is state-independent iff there exists some function  U:X\rightarrow\Re, such that  u\left( x,t\right) =U\left( x\right) , for all  x and  t.

Theorem 10   The eight axioms are jointly satisfied if and only if there exists a utility function  u:X\times\Omega\rightarrow\Re and a conditional-probability function  p:\Xi\rightarrow\Delta\left( \Omega\right) such that:
\displaystyle \max_{x\in X}u\left( x,t\right) \displaystyle =1 and \displaystyle \min_{x\in X}u\left( x,t\right) =0,\forall t\in\Omega;    
\displaystyle p\left( R\mid T\right) \displaystyle =p\left( R\mid S\right) p\left( S\mid T\right) ,    
\displaystyle \forall R,\forall S,\forall T \displaystyle :R\subseteq S\subseteq T\subseteq \Omega,S\neq\emptyset;    
\displaystyle f \displaystyle \succsim_{S}g iff \displaystyle E_{p}\left[ u\left( f\right) \mid S\right] \geq E_{p}\left[ u\left( g\right) \mid S\right] ,    
\displaystyle \forall f,g \displaystyle \in L,\forall S\in\Xi,    

where  E_{p}\left[ u\left( f\right) \mid S\right] =\sum_{t\in S}p\left( t\mid S\right) \sum_{x\in X}u\left( x,t\right) f\left( x\mid t\right) is the expected utility value of the prize determined by  f, when  p\left( \cdot\mid S\right) is the probability distribution for the true state of the world.
Proof. see Myerson (1991).  \qedsymbol

Discussion and caveats

Axiom 11 (State neutrality)   For any two states  r and  t in  \Omega, if  f\left( \cdot\mid t\right) =f\left( \cdot\mid t\right) and  g\left( \cdot\mid t\right) =g\left( \cdot\mid t\right) and  f\succsim_{r}g, then  f\succsim_{t}g.
Theorem 12   Given the axioms above, state neutrality is also satisfied if and only if the conditions of the representation theorem can be satisfied with a state-independent utility function.
Proof. see Myerson (1991).  \qedsymbol

Definition, existence and uniqueness of the equilibrium solution

This Appendix provides a more formal definition of equilibrium for an exchange economy populated by investors with happiness maintenance preferences. It also contains a proof that such equilibrium exists.

Definition of equilibrium

Equilibrium is defined by a pair of functions,  p:\Re^{+}\rightarrow\Re^{+}, the asset pricing function, and  v(s,y,\theta;p), a value function, such that:

  1.  v:\Re^{+}\times\Re^{+}\rightarrow\Re^{+};v(s,y,\theta;p(\circ))=\max E_{0}\left[ \sum_{t=0}^{\infty}\beta^{t}u\left( g_{t}\right) \right] , subject to  c_{t}+p_{t}s_{t+1}\leq s_{t}(p_{t}+y_{t}) given  F\left( \cdot\right) ,  s_{0}=\widehat{s}_{0}<1,y_{0},\theta_{0}.
  2.  s_{t+1}=s_{t}=1,  c_{t}=y_{t}.

Euler equations and returns

The functional equation associated with the investor's maximization problem is:

\displaystyle V\left( s_{t},y_{t},\theta_{t}\right) \displaystyle =\max_{\left\{ c_{t}% ,s_{t+1}\right\} }\left\{ u(g\left( c_{t},w_{t};\theta_{t}\right) )+\beta E_{t}V\left( s_{t+1},y_{t+1},\theta_{t+1}\right) \right\}    
\displaystyle c_{t}+p_{t}s_{t+1} \displaystyle =\left( p_{t}+y_{t}\right) s_{t}=w_{t}    
\displaystyle c_{t} \displaystyle >0, \displaystyle s_{t+1}\in\left( 0,1\right] , and \displaystyle s_{0}% ,y_{0} \displaystyle \theta_{0} given\displaystyle %    

where  E_{t}\left( x_{t}\right) =\int x_{t}dF\left( y_{t+1},x_{t+1}% ;y_{t},x_{t}\right) is the expectation operator. The first order and envelope conditions are respectively:
\displaystyle u_{c}\left( g\left( \left( p_{t}+y_{t}\right) s_{t}-p_{t}s_{t+1},\left( p_{t}+y_{t}\right) s_{t};\theta_{t}\right) \right) p_{t}=\beta E_{t}% V_{1}\left( s_{t+1},y_{t+1},\theta_{t+1}\right)    
\displaystyle V_{1}\left( s_{t},y_{t},\theta_{t}\right) =u_{c}\left( g\left( \left( p_{t}+y_{t}\right) s_{t}-p_{t}s_{t+1},\left( p_{t}+y_{t}\right) s_{t};\theta_{t}\right) \right) \left( p_{t}+y_{t}\right)    
\displaystyle +u_{w}\left( g\left( \left( p_{t}+y_{t}\right) s_{t}-p_{t}s_{t+1},\left( p_{t}+y_{t}\right) s_{t};\theta_{t}\right) \right) \left( p_{t}% +y_{t}\right)    

where  V_{1} is the derivative of the value function with respect to  s_{t}.

Substituting back for consumption from the budget constraint and using the definition of  w_{t}, the Euler equation % latex2html id marker 6018 $ \left( \ref{eulero}\right) $ can be written as

  \displaystyle \left( 1-\theta_{t}\right) c_{t}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( 1-\theta_{t}\right) -1}w_{t}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t}}p_{t}    
  \displaystyle =\beta E_{t}\left\{ \left[ \begin{array}[c]{c}% \left( 1-\theta_{t+1}\right) c_{t+1}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( 1-\theta_{t+1}\right) -1}w_{t+1}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t+1}}\\ +\theta_{t+1}c_{t+1}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( 1-\theta_{t+1}\right) }w_{t+1}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t+1}-1}% \end{array} \right] \left( p_{t+1}+y_{t+1}\right) \right\}    
  \displaystyle \left( 1-\theta_{t}\right) c_{t}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( 1-\theta_{t}\right) -1}w_{t}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t}}p_{t}    
  \displaystyle =\beta E_{t}\left\{ \left( 1-\theta_{t+1}\right) c_{t+1}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( 1-\theta_{t+1}\right) -1}w_{t+1}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t+1}}\left( 1+\frac{\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t+1}% }\frac{c_{t+1}}{w_{t+1}}\right) \left( p_{t+1}+y_{t+1}\right) \right\}    

Simple algebraic manipulations deliver the Euler equation % latex2html id marker 6024 $ \left( \ref{re0}\right) $ that appears in the text.

Premium

For the expected premium, using the definition of the risk-free rate I have

\displaystyle 1 \displaystyle =\beta E\left[ \left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( 1-\theta_{t}\right) -1}\left( \frac{w_{t+1}}{w_{t}% }\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t}}k_{t+1}\left( \frac{c_{t+1}% }{w_{t+1}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( \theta_{t}-\theta _{t+1}\right) }\right] ER_{t+1}    
  \displaystyle +cov\left( \left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha \right) \left( 1-\theta_{t}\right) -1}\left( \frac{w_{t+1}}{w_{t}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t}}k_{t+1}\left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{w_{t+1}% }\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( \theta_{t}-\theta_{t+1}\right) },R_{t+1}\right)    
\displaystyle 1 \displaystyle =\frac{ER_{t+1}}{R_{f}}    
  \displaystyle +cov\left( \left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha \right) \left( 1-\theta_{t}\right) -1}\left( \frac{w_{t+1}}{w_{t}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t}}k_{t+1}\left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{w_{t+1}% }\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( \theta_{t}-\theta_{t+1}\right) },R_{t+1}\right)    

\displaystyle R_{f} \displaystyle =ER_{t+1}+R_{f}cov\left( m_{t+1},R_{t+1}\right)    
\displaystyle ER_{t+1}-R_{f} \displaystyle =R_{f}cov\left( -m_{t+1},R_{t+1}\right)    

where  m_{t+1}=\left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha \right) \left( 1-\theta_{t}\right) -1}\left( \frac{w_{t+1}}{w_{t}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t}}k_{t+1}\left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{w_{t+1}% }\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( \theta_{t}-\theta_{t+1}\right) }.

Existence of equilibrium

This section proves the existence of a (bounded and strictly positive) equilibrium price-dividend function for probability structure % latex2html id marker 6040 $ \left( \ref{probabilita1}\right) .$ The main complication in establishing existence derives from the endogeneity of the pricing kernel induced by the dependence of the utility function on wealth and, in equilibrium, on the price-dividend function. Such endogeneity prevents us from characterizing the Euler equation as a non-linear counterpart of the linear Fredholm equations much studied in the consumption-based asset pricing tradition.

Under the assumed probability structure, the Euler equation defines the following system of two non-linear equations in two unknown price-dividend ratio functions:

\displaystyle f_{1}\left( f_{1}+1\right) ^{-a_{1}}-\beta\left[ \begin{array}[c]{c}% \pi_{11}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1-\frac{a_{1}}{1-\alpha}\frac{1}% {f_{1}+1}\right) \left( f_{1}+1\right) ^{1-a_{1}}\\ +\pi_{12}\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1-\frac{a_{2}}{1-\alpha}\frac{1}% {f_{2}+1}\right) \left( f_{2}+1\right) ^{1-a_{2}}% \end{array} \right] \displaystyle =0 (13)
\displaystyle f_{2}\left( f_{2}+1\right) ^{-a_{2}}-\beta\left[ \begin{array}[c]{c}% \pi_{21}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1-\frac{a_{1}}{1-\alpha}\frac{1}% {f_{1}+1}\right) \left( f_{1}+1\right) ^{1-a_{1}}\\ +\pi_{22}\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1-\frac{a_{2}}{1-\alpha}\frac{1}% {f_{2}+1}\right) \left( f_{2}+1\right) ^{1-a_{2}}% \end{array} \right] \displaystyle =0    

where
\begin{displaymath} \left[ \begin{array}[c]{cc}% \pi_{11} & \pi_{12}\ \pi_{21} & \pi_{22}% \end{array}\right] \equiv\left[ \begin{array}[c]{cc}% \pi & 1-\pi\ 1-\pi & \pi \end{array}\right] \end{displaymath}

To simplify notation, I notice that % latex2html id marker 6048 $ \left( \ref{EE1}\right) $ can be rewritten as

\displaystyle f_{1}\left( f_{1}+1\right) ^{-a_{1}}-\beta\left[ \begin{array}[c]{c}% \pi_{11}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( f_{1}+1+\gamma_{1}\right) \left( f_{1}+1\right) ^{-a_{1}}\\ +\pi_{12}\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( f_{2}+1+\gamma_{2}\right) \left( f_{2}+1\right) ^{-a_{2}}% \end{array} \right] \displaystyle =0    
\displaystyle f_{2}\left( f_{2}+1\right) ^{-a_{2}}-\beta\left[ \begin{array}[c]{c}% \pi_{21}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( f_{1}+1+\gamma_{1}\right) \left( f_{1}+1\right) ^{-a_{1}}\\ +\pi_{22}\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( f_{2}+1+\gamma_{2}\right) \left( f_{2}+1\right) ^{-a_{2}}% \end{array} \right] \displaystyle =0    

\displaystyle f_{1}-\beta\left[ \pi_{11}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( f_{1}+1+\gamma _{1}\right) +\pi_{12}\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( f_{2}+1+\gamma_{2}\right) \frac{\left( f_{2}+1\right) ^{-a_{2}}}{\left( f_{1}+1\right) ^{-a_{1}}% }\right] \displaystyle =0    
\displaystyle f_{2}-\beta\left[ \pi_{21}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( f_{1}+1+\gamma _{1}\right) \frac{\left( f_{1}+1\right) ^{-a_{1}}}{\left( f_{2}+1\right) ^{-a_{2}}}+\pi_{22}\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( f_{2}+1+\gamma_{2}\right) \right] \displaystyle =0    

\displaystyle x_{1}-\beta\left[ \pi_{11}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{1}+\gamma _{1}\right) +\pi_{12}\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{2}+\gamma_{2}\right) \frac{x_{2}^{-a_{2}}}{x_{1}^{-a_{1}}}\right] -1 \displaystyle =0    
\displaystyle x_{2}-\beta\left[ \pi_{21}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{1}+\gamma _{1}\right) \frac{x_{1}^{-a_{1}}}{x_{2}^{-a_{2}}}+\pi_{22}\lambda _{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{2}+\gamma_{2}\right) \right] -1 \displaystyle =0    

\displaystyle x_{1}-\beta\left[ \pi_{11}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{1}+\gamma _{1}\right) +\left( 1-\pi_{11}\right) \lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{2}+\gamma_{2}\right) \frac{x_{1}^{a_{1}}}{x_{2}^{a_{2}}}\right] -1 \displaystyle =0    
\displaystyle x_{2}-\beta\left[ \pi_{21}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{1}+\gamma _{1}\right) \frac{x_{2}^{a_{2}}}{x_{1}^{a_{1}}}+\left( 1-\pi_{21}\right) \lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{2}+\gamma_{2}\right) \right] -1 \displaystyle =0    

where  x_{1}\equiv f_{1}+1 and  x_{2}\equiv f_{2}+1. I can than denote % latex2html id marker 6070 $ \left( \ref{EE1}\right) $ as
\begin{displaymath} G\left( x,\phi\right) =\left[ \begin{array}[c]{c}% G_{1}\left( x,\pi_{1}\right) \ G_{2}\left( x,\pi_{2}\right) \end{array}\right] =0 \end{displaymath}
where  x\equiv\left( x_{1},x_{2}\right) ,  \phi\equiv\left( \pi_{1}% ,\pi_{2}\right) ,  \pi_{1}\equiv\left( \pi_{11},\pi_{12}\right) ,  \pi_{2}\equiv\left( \pi_{21},\pi_{22}\right) .

I resort to a fixed point argument (see Milnor (1997) for a detailed treatment) to show that a solution to  G exists.

It is understood that all parameters other than the probabilities are taken as given. Let

\displaystyle \zeta=\left\{ \left( x,\phi\right) \mid G\left( x,\phi\right) =0\right\} \subset\mathbb{R}^{2}\times\left( \Delta\right) ^{2}%

I start by proving the following

Lemma 13    \zeta is a smooth manifold.
Proof. By perturbing  G with respect to  \pi_{1}, I need to show that, for an arbitrarily fixed open and full Lebesgue set of parameter values  \left( \beta,\lambda_{1},\lambda_{2},\alpha,a\right) , the Jacobian of the map  G with respect to  \pi and  x,  D_{\pi,x}G, has full rank. To this end I study the Jacobian of the map  G with respect to  \pi and  x. By definition, I have
\begin{displaymath} D_{\pi,x}G=\left[ \begin{array}[c]{cc}% \alpha\left( \lambda_{1}\right) -\alpha\left( \lambda_{2}\right) & 0\ 0 & \hat{\alpha}\left( \lambda_{1}\right) -\hat{\alpha}\left( \lambda _{2}\right) \end{array}\right] \end{displaymath}

where I define  \alpha\left( \lambda_{1}\right) \equiv\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha }\left( x_{1}+\gamma_{1}\right) ,  \alpha\left( \lambda_{2}\right) \equiv\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{2}+\gamma_{2}\right) \frac {x_{1}^{a_{1}}}{x_{2}^{a_{2}}},
 \hat{\alpha}\left( \lambda _{1}\right) \equiv\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{1}+\gamma_{1}\right) \frac{x_{2}^{a_{2}}}{x_{1}^{a_{1}}},  \hat{\alpha}\left( \lambda_{2}\right) \equiv\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{2}+\gamma_{2}\right) .

Evidently,  D_{\pi,x}G is onto if  \alpha\left( \lambda_{1}\right) -\alpha\left( \lambda_{2}\right) \neq0 (or, equivalently,  \alpha\left( \lambda_{1}\right) \neq\alpha\left( \lambda_{2}\right) ) and  \hat{\alpha }\left( \lambda_{1}\right) -\hat{\alpha}\left( \lambda_{2}\right) \neq0 (or, equivalently,  \hat{\alpha}\left( \lambda_{1}\right) \neq\hat{\alpha }\left( \lambda_{2}\right) ). However,

\displaystyle \alpha\left( \lambda_{1}\right) =\alpha\left( \lambda_{2}\right) \Leftrightarrow\hat{\alpha}\left( \lambda_{1}\right) =\hat{\alpha}\left( \lambda_{2}\right)

Suppose, then, that these equalities hold. % latex2html id marker 6138 $ \left( \ref{EE1}\right) $ simplifies to

\displaystyle x_{1} \displaystyle =\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{1}+\gamma_{1}\right) +1    
\displaystyle x_{2} \displaystyle =\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{1}+\gamma_{1}\right) \frac{x_{2}^{a_{2}}}{x_{1}^{a_{1}}}+1    

By taking the ratio, I obtain

\displaystyle \frac{x_{1}-1}{x_{2}-1}=\frac{x_{1}^{a_{1}}}{x_{2}^{a_{2}}}% (14)

I need to verify the existence of an open and full Lebesgue measure set of parameter values such that

\displaystyle \frac{x_{1}-1}{x_{2}-1}\neq\frac{x_{1}^{a_{1}}}{x_{2}^{a_{2}}}%

When  \pi_{11}=1 and  \pi_{21}=0 % latex2html id marker 6152 $ \left( \ref{EE1}\right) $ simplifies to

\displaystyle x_{1}-1 \displaystyle =\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}x_{1}+\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha }\gamma_{1}    
\displaystyle x_{2}-1 \displaystyle =\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}x_{2}+\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha }\gamma_{2}%    

\displaystyle x_{1}-\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}x_{1} \displaystyle =\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}% \gamma_{1}+1    
\displaystyle x_{2}-\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}x_{2} \displaystyle =\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}% \gamma_{2}+1    

\displaystyle x_{i}\left( 1-\beta\lambda_{i}^{1-\alpha}\right) \displaystyle =\beta\lambda _{i}^{1-\alpha}\gamma_{i}+1    
\displaystyle x_{i} \displaystyle =\frac{\beta\lambda_{i}^{1-\alpha}\gamma_{i}+1}{1-\beta\lambda _{i}^{1-\alpha}}%    

\displaystyle x_{1} \displaystyle =\frac{\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\gamma_{1}+1}{1-\beta\lambda _{1}^{1-\alpha}}\equiv x_{1}^{\ast}    
\displaystyle x_{2} \displaystyle =\frac{\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\gamma_{2}+1}{1-\beta\lambda _{2}^{1-\alpha}}\equiv x_{2}^{\ast}%    

and
\displaystyle x_{1}^{\ast}-1 \displaystyle =\frac{\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\gamma _{1}\right) }{1-\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}}    
\displaystyle x_{2}^{\ast}-1 \displaystyle =\frac{\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\gamma _{2}\right) }{1-\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}}%    

Thus
\displaystyle \frac{x_{1}^{\ast}-1}{x_{2}^{\ast}-1}=\frac{\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\gamma_{1}\right) \left( 1-\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\right) }% {\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\gamma_{2}\right) \left( 1-\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\right) }%
and
\displaystyle \frac{\left( x_{1}^{\ast}\right) ^{a_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{\ast}\right) ^{a_{2}}}=\left( \frac{\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\gamma _{1}\right) }{1-\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}}\right) ^{a_{1}}\left( \frac{1-\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}}{\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\gamma_{2}\right) }\right) ^{a_{2}}%

Consider now the function

\displaystyle H\left( x,a\right) =\frac{x_{1}^{\ast}-1}{x_{2}^{\ast}-1}-\frac{\left( x_{1}^{\ast}\right) ^{a_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{\ast}\right) ^{a_{2}}}%

It is straightforward to show that  \frac{\partial H}{\partial a}\neq0. In fact, I have

\displaystyle \frac{\partial H}{\partial a} \displaystyle =-\frac{\left( x_{1}^{\ast}\right) ^{a_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{\ast}\right) ^{a_{2}}}\log\frac{\left( x_{1}^{\ast }\right) ^{\lambda_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{\ast}\right) ^{\lambda_{2}}}    
  \displaystyle =-\frac{\left( x_{1}^{\ast}\right) ^{a_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{\ast}\right) ^{a_{2}}}\left( \lambda_{1}\log x_{1}^{\ast}-\lambda_{2}\log x_{2}^{\ast }\right)    

Clearly, there exists an open and full Lebesgue measure set of parameter values  \left( \beta,\lambda_{1},\lambda_{2},\alpha,a\right) such that  \frac{\partial H}{\partial a}\neq0 or, equivalently,  \zeta is a smooth manifold.  \qedsymbol

Lemma 14   There exists a regular value of the map  proj\left( \zeta\right) \rightarrow\Delta,  \pi^{\ast} such that

 \char93 \left[ proj^{-1}\left( \pi^{\ast}\right) \right] =odd.

Proof. Fix  \pi_{11}=1 and  \pi_{21}=0. Then % latex2html id marker 6209 $ \left( \ref{EE1}\right) $ simplifies to a system of two linear equations
\displaystyle x_{1}-1 \displaystyle =\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}x_{1}+\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha }\gamma_{1}    
\displaystyle x_{2}-1 \displaystyle =\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}x_{2}+\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha }\gamma_{2}%    

\displaystyle x_{1} \displaystyle =\frac{\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\gamma_{1}\right) }{1-\beta\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}}+1    
\displaystyle x_{2} \displaystyle =\frac{\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\gamma_{2}\right) }{1-\beta\lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}}+1    

Clearly, the solution is unique.  \qedsymbol

Lemma 15   The map  proj\left( \zeta\right) \rightarrow\Delta is proper, that is  proj^{-1}\left( \pi\right) is compact for each compact subset of probability.
Proof. It suffices to show that  1<proj^{-1}\left( \pi\right) <\infty.

Suppose that (without loss of generality)  x_{1}=1. Then

\displaystyle \beta\left[ \pi_{11}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\gamma_{1}\right) +\left( 1-\pi_{11}\right) \lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( x_{2}+\gamma _{2}\right) \frac{1}{x_{2}^{a_{2}}}\right] =0
which is obviously impossible.

Suppose, by contradiction, that  \exists\pi^{n}\rightarrow\pi^{h} such that  \left\Vert x^{h}\right\Vert \equiv\left\Vert x\left( \pi^{h}\right) \right\Vert \rightarrow\infty. I distinguish two cases ( \infty is symmetric to zero and therefore ignored):

  1.  \frac{\left( x_{1}^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}}}\rightarrow K>0

    The second equation becomes

    \displaystyle 1=\beta\left[ \pi_{21}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( \frac{x_{1}^{h}}% {x_{2}^{h}}+\frac{\gamma_{1}}{x_{2}^{h}}\right) \frac{\left( x_{2}% ^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}}}{\left( x_{1}^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}}}+\left( 1-\pi _{21}\right) \lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\frac{\gamma_{2}}{x_{2}^{h}% }\right) \right] +\frac{1}{x_{2}^{h}}%
    thus in the limit
    \displaystyle 1=\beta\left[ \pi_{21}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\lim_{h\rightarrow\infty}\left( \frac{x_{1}^{h}}{x_{2}^{h}}\right) K^{-1}+\left( 1-\pi_{21}\right) \lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\right]

    The first equation (again dividing by  x_{1} and taking the limit) becomes

    \displaystyle 1 \displaystyle =\beta\left[ \pi_{11}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\frac{\gamma_{1}% }{x_{1}^{h}}\right) +\left( 1-\pi_{11}\right) \lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\left( \frac{x_{2}^{h}}{x_{1}^{h}}+\frac{\gamma_{2}}{x_{1}^{h}}\right) \frac{\left( x_{1}^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}}}\right] +\frac{1}{x_{1}^{h}}    
    \displaystyle 1 \displaystyle =\beta\left[ \pi_{11}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}+\left( 1-\pi_{11}\right) \lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\lim_{h\rightarrow\infty}\left( \frac{x_{2}^{h}}% {x_{1}^{h}}\right) K\right]    

    Since  \left\Vert x^{h}\right\Vert \rightarrow\infty and  \frac{\left( x_{1}% ^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}}}\rightarrow K>0, then  x_{1}^{h}\rightarrow\infty and  x_{2}^{h}\rightarrow\infty. Since  a_{1}\neq a_{2}, either  \lim_{h\rightarrow\infty}\left( \frac{x_{2}^{h}% }{x_{1}^{h}}\right) =\infty or  \lim_{h\rightarrow\infty}\left( \frac {x_{1}^{h}}{x_{2}^{h}}\right) =\infty. Hence,  \frac{\left( x_{1}% ^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}}}\rightarrow K>0 is impossible.

  2.  \frac{\left( x_{1}^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}}}\rightarrow0

    By repeating the same procedure, I have

    \displaystyle 1 \displaystyle =\beta\left[ \pi_{11}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}+\left( 1-\pi_{11}\right) \lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\lim_{h\rightarrow\infty}\frac{\left( x_{1}^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}-1}}{\left( x_{2}^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}-1}}\right]    
    \displaystyle 1 \displaystyle =\beta\left[ \pi_{21}\lambda_{1}^{1-\alpha}\lim_{h\rightarrow\infty }\frac{\left( x_{2}^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}-1}}{\left( x_{1}^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}-1}}+\left( 1-\pi_{21}\right) \lambda_{2}^{1-\alpha}\right]    

    If  \frac{\left( x_{1}^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}}}\rightarrow0, then either  \lim_{h\rightarrow\infty}\frac{\left( x_{1}^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}-1}}{\left( x_{2}^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}-1}}=0 or  \lim_{h\rightarrow\infty}\frac{\left( x_{1}^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}-1}}{\left( x_{2}^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}-1}}=\infty. Hence  \frac{\left( x_{1}^{h}\right) ^{a_{1}}}{\left( x_{2}^{h}\right) ^{a_{2}}}\rightarrow0 is impossible.

 \qedsymbol

I are now in a position to state the following

Theorem 16   There exists a bounded and strictly positive equilibrium price-dividend function for probability structure % latex2html id marker 6290 $ \left( \ref{probabilita1}% \right) $
Proof. The statement follows directly from Lemmas 13-15.  \qedsymbol

Computation of returns

To write the Euler as a (nonlinear) first order difference equation in the price-dividend ratio, recall

\displaystyle 1=\beta E\left[ \frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t}}\left( \frac{c_{t+1}% }{c_{t}}\right) ^{-\alpha}\frac{\left( w_{t+1}/c_{t+1}\right) ^{-a_{t+1}}% }{\left( w_{t}/c_{t}\right) ^{-a_{t}}}\left( 1+\frac{\theta_{t+1}}% {1-\theta_{t+1}}\frac{c_{t+1}}{w_{t+1}}\right) R_{t+1}\right]

Define  f_{t}=\frac{p_{t}}{y_{t}} to be the price-dividend ratio and observe that in equilibrium I can write  w_{t}=\left( f_{t}+1\right) y_{t}. The Euler, then, becomes

\displaystyle 1=\beta E\left[ \frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t}}\left( \frac{c_{t+1}% }{c_{t}}\right) ^{-\alpha}\frac{\left( f_{t+1}+1\right) ^{-a_{t+1}}% }{\left( f_{t}+1\right) ^{-a_{t}}}\left( 1+\frac{\theta_{t+1}}% {1-\theta_{t+1}}\frac{c_{t+1}}{\left( f_{t+1}+1\right) y_{t+1}}\right) R_{t+1}\right]    
\displaystyle 1=\beta E\left[ \frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t}}\left( \frac{c_{t+1}% }{c_{t}}\right) ^{-\alpha}\frac{\left( f_{t+1}+1\right) ^{-a_{t+1}}% }{\left( f_{t}+1\right) ^{-a_{t}}}\left( 1+\frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}% {1-\theta_{t}}\frac{1}{f_{t+1}+1}\right) R_{t+1}\right]    

since by definition returns are  R_{t+1}=\frac{p_{t+1}+y_{t+1}}{p_{t}}% =\frac{\left( \frac{p_{t+1}}{y_{t+1}}+1\right) y_{t+1}}{\frac{p_{t}}{y_{t}% }y_{t}}=\frac{f_{t+1}+1}{f_{t}}\frac{y_{t+1}}{y_{t}}, I have
\displaystyle 1=\beta E\left[ \frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t}}\left( \frac{c_{t+1}% }{c_{t}}\right) ^{-\alpha}\frac{\left( f_{t+1}+1\right) ^{-a_{t+1}}% }{\left( f_{t}+1\right) ^{-a_{t}}}\left( 1+\frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}% {1-\theta_{t}}\frac{1}{f_{t+1}+1}\right) \frac{f_{t+1}+1}{f_{t}}\frac {y_{t+1}}{y_{t}}\right]    
\displaystyle 1=\beta E\left[ \frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t}}\left( \frac{c_{t+1}% }{c_{t}}\right) ^{1-\alpha}\frac{\left( f_{t+1}+1\right) ^{-a_{t+1}}% }{\left( f_{t}+1\right) ^{-a_{t}}}\left( 1+\frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}% {1-\theta_{t}}\frac{1}{f_{t+1}+1}\right) \frac{f_{t+1}+1}{f_{t}}\right]    

Hence, the Euler can be rewritten as

\displaystyle f_{t}\left( f_{t}+1\right) ^{-a_{t}}=\beta E\left[ \frac{1-\theta_{t+1}% }{1-\theta_{t}}\left( \frac{c_{t+1}}{c_{t}}\right) ^{1-\alpha}\left( 1+\frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t}}\frac{1}{f_{t+1}+1}\right) \left( f_{t+1}+1\right) ^{1-a_{t+1}}\right]

Hedonic Relative Risk Aversion

Consider the a-temporal case where the outcome  l\in L is independent of the preference state  s\in S, with probabilities given by  P_{l} and  P_{s} respectively. It is straightforward to derive the hedonic risk aversion of the investor by using the definition of relative risk aversion . In fact,

\displaystyle u\left( g\right) \displaystyle =EU\left( C,W/C,S\right)    
  \displaystyle =\sum_{l\in L}\sum_{s\in S}P_{l}P_{s}C_{l}^{1-\alpha}\frac{W/C_{l}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{s}}}{1-\alpha}    
  \displaystyle =\sum_{l\in L}P_{l}\mathcal{V}\left( W/C_{l}\right)    

where  \mathcal{V}\left( W/C_{l}\right) =\sum_{s\in S}P_{s}C_{l}^{1-\alpha }\frac{W/C_{l}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{s}}}{1-\alpha} is the state independent utility function, that is a linear combination with positive weights of conditionally isoelastic concave functions, and thus concave. Moreover, given that  S and  L are orthogonal, the curvature of  \mathcal{V}\left( W/C_{l}\right) captures the investors' attitude toward atemporal risk. Hence, the Arrow-Pratt coefficient of relative risk aversion with respect to (wealth relative to consumption) lotteries on  L is
\displaystyle RRA_{W/C}=-W/C\frac{\mathcal{V}_{WW}}{\mathcal{V}_{w}}%
\displaystyle \mathcal{V}_{W} \displaystyle =\sum_{s\in S}P_{s}C_{l}^{1-\alpha}\theta_{s}% W/C_{l}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{s}-1}    
\displaystyle \mathcal{V}_{WW} \displaystyle =\sum_{s\in S}P_{s}C_{l}^{1-\alpha}\theta_{s}\left( \left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{s}-1\right) W/C_{l}^{\left( 1-\alpha \right) \theta_{s}-2}    
\displaystyle RRA_{W} \displaystyle =-W/C\frac{\sum_{s\in S}P_{s}C_{l}^{1-\alpha}\theta_{s}\left( \left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{s}-1\right) W/C_{l}^{\left( 1-\alpha \right) \theta_{s}-2}}{\sum_{s\in S}P_{s}C_{l}^{1-\alpha}\theta_{s}% W/C_{l}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{s}-1}}    
  \displaystyle =-\sum_{s\in S}\left( \left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{s}-1\right)    
  \displaystyle =\sum_{s\in S}\left( \left( \alpha-1\right) \theta_{s}+1\right)    

If preferences are state-independent, i.e.  \theta_{s}=\theta  \forall s, then the coefficient of relative risk aversion is constant and equal to  \left( \alpha-1\right) \theta+1. The coefficient of relative risk aversion for lotteries that are conditional on the realization of a given state  s is  \left( \alpha-1\right) \theta_{s}+1. Since each period is associated with a single preference state,  \left( \alpha-1\right) \theta_{t}+1 can be interpreted as the coefficient of relative risk aversion for static lotteries.

Intertemporal elasticity of substitution

Recall the Euler

\displaystyle 1=\beta E\left[ g_{c}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( 1-\theta_{t}\right) -1}g_{w}^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \theta_{t}}k_{t+1}\left( \frac{c_{t+1}% }{w_{t+1}}\right) ^{\left( 1-\alpha\right) \left( \theta_{t}-\theta _{t+1}\right) }R_{t+1}\right]
where  g_{c}=\frac{c_{t+1}}{c_{t}} and  g_{w}=\frac{w_{t+1}}{w_{t}}. and  k_{t+1}\equiv\left( \frac{1-\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t}}\right) \left( 1+\frac{\theta_{t+1}}{1-\theta_{t+1}}\frac{c_{t+1}}{w_{t+1}}\right) Along a balanced growth path with constant interest rates I have  g_{c}=g_{w}=g and the Euler becomes
\displaystyle 1 \displaystyle =\beta\left( g^{-\alpha}+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}g^{-\alpha}\frac{c}% {w}\right) \left( 1+r\right)    
\displaystyle 1 \displaystyle =\beta g^{-\alpha}\left( 1+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}\frac{c}{w}\right) \left( 1+r\right)    

It is straightforward to observe that if I take the term  \frac{c}{w} as exogenous and ignore the dependence of wealth on returns, then

\displaystyle \frac{dg}{dr}=\frac{1}{\alpha}%

Nevertheless, using the investors' budget constraint

\displaystyle \frac{w_{t+1}}{w_{t}}=R_{t+1}\left( 1-\frac{c_{t}}{w_{t}}\right)
and the balanced growth path assumption I can write
\displaystyle g=\left( 1+r\right) \left( 1-\frac{c}{w}\right)
which provides  \frac{c}{w} as the following function of  r
\displaystyle \frac{c}{w}=1-\frac{g}{1+r}%
substituting for  \frac{c}{w} into the Euler I have
\displaystyle 1=\beta g^{-\alpha}\left( 1+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}\left( 1-\frac{g}% {1+r}\right) \right) \left( 1+r\right)

Taking logs I have

0 \displaystyle =\log\beta-\alpha\log g+\log\left( 1+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}\left( 1-\frac{g}{1+r}\right) \right) +\log\left( 1+r\right)    
0 \displaystyle \approx\left( \beta-1\right) -\alpha\left( g-1\right) +\frac{\theta }{1-\theta}\left( 1-\frac{g}{1+r}\right) +r    
\displaystyle g \displaystyle =\frac{\beta-1+\alpha+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}+r}{\alpha+\frac{\theta }{1-\theta}\frac{1}{1+r}}%    

Hence, the elasticity of intertemporal substitution is

\displaystyle \frac{dg}{dr} \displaystyle =\frac{\alpha+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}\frac{1}{1+r}+\left( \beta-1+\alpha+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}+r\right) \frac{\theta}{1-\theta}% \frac{1}{\left( 1+r\right) ^{2}}}{\left( \alpha+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta }\frac{1}{1+r}\right) ^{2}}    
  \displaystyle =\frac{1}{\alpha+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}\frac{1}{1+r}}\left[ 1+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}\frac{\beta-1+\alpha+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}% +r}{\left( \alpha+\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}\frac{1}{1+r}\right) \left( 1+r\right) ^{2}}\right]    

Appendix B: Tables and Figures

Table 1 - Summary of unconditional first and second moments of returns in the benchmark calibration

  US data
(MP sample)
US data
1891-1998
US data
1947-1998
HM, iid:

 \theta=.26,\beta=0.97

HM, Markov:

 \theta=.25,\beta =0.99

 E\left( R^{f}\right) 0.80 1.91 0.90 1.77 0.84
 E\left( R^{e}\right) 6.98 7.91 8.08 7.81 6.95
 E\left( R^{ep}\right) 6.18 6.00 7.18 6.03 6.11
 \sigma\left( R^{f}\right) 5.44 5.44 1.75 2.22 5.55
 \sigma\left( R^{e}\right) 19.02 18.60 15.65 22.82 23.17
 \sigma\left( R^{ep}\right) 18.53 18.50 15.27 22.61 22.57
 E\left( P/D\right) 23.75 23.75 28.31 28.34 38.12
 \sigma\left( P/D\right) 7.6 7.6 11.5 7.16 6.4
 \frac{E\left( R^{ep}\right) }{\sigma\left( R^{ep}\right) } 0.33 0.32 0.47 0.34 0.27

Note: This table reports historical data and model-implied moments of financial variables for various assets. All statistics are annualized and in percent terms. The financial variables are the riskfree rate,  R^{f} , the equity return,  R^{e}, the excess return of equity over the riskfree rate,  R^{ep} , and the price to dividend ratio,  P/D. The moments are mean,  E , and standard deviation,  \sigma . The historical data for the MP sample is from Mehra and Prescott (1985) and covers the 1889-1985 period. Otherwise, historical data is from Campbell (1999). The only difference in the calibration of columns "HM, iid" and "HM, Markov" is the specification of the process for (log) consumption growth under which the happiness maintenance model is solved. The process is specified as iid lognormal for "HM, iid" (specification % latex2html id marker 6493 $ \left( \ref{probabilita2}\right) $ in the text) and Markov for "HM, Markov" (specification % latex2html id marker 6495 $ \left( \ref{probabilita1}\right) $ in the text).

Parameter values:  \alpha=3,  n=2,\mu=0.018,  \delta=0.036,  \pi=0.43.

Implied hedonic risk aversion:  E\left( a_{t+1}\right) =1.5;  \sigma\left( a_{t+1}\right) =0.009;  a_{t\max}=1.52;  a_{t\min }=1.48.

Table 2 - Summary of unconditional first and second moments of returns when  \theta_{t}=\theta_{t+1}

  US data: (MP sample) US data: 1891-1998 US data: 1947-1998 No Happiness: (  \theta_{t}=\theta_{t+1}=0) No HM: (  \theta_{t}=\theta _{t+1}=0.25)
 E\left( R^{f}\right) 0.80 1.91 0.90 5.74 4.64
 E\left( R^{e}\right) 6.98 7.91 8.08 6.22 5.24
 E\left( R^{ep}\right) 6.18 6.00 7.18 0.48 0.60
 \sigma\left( R^{f}\right) 5.44 5.44 1.75 1.57 2.20
 \sigma\left( R^{e}\right) 19.02 18.60 15.65 4.87 5.65
 \sigma\left( R^{ep}\right) 18.53 18.50 15.27 4.60 5.20
 \frac{E\left( R^{ep}\right) }{\sigma\left( R^{ep}\right) } 0.33 0.32 0.47 0.10 0.11

Note: This table reports historical data and model-implied moments of financial variables for various assets. All statistics are annualized and in percent terms. The financial variables are the riskfree rate,  R^{f} , the equity return,  R^{e}, the excess return of equity over the riskfree rate,  R^{ep} , and the price to dividend ratio,  P/D. The moments are mean,  E , and standard deviation,  \sigma . The historical data for the MP sample is from Mehra and Prescott (1985) and covers the 1889-1985 period. Otherwise, historical data is from Campbell (1999). The difference between columns "No Happiness" and "No HM" is in the calibration of the hedonic risk aversion parameter,  \theta_{t}, under which the happiness maintenance model is solved. The parameter is set equal to zero in column "No Happiness" and as a constant equal to 0.25 in column "No HM".

Parameter values:  \alpha=3,  \mu=0.018,  \delta=0.036,  \pi=0.43.

Table 3 - Inspecting the mechanism:  a_{t}

   E\left( R^{f}\right)  E\left( R^{ep}\right)  \frac{E\left( R^{ep}\right) }{\sigma\left( R^{ep}\right) }
US data 0.80 6.18 0.32
 \alpha=2,  \theta=0.42 0.21 4.27 0.23
 \alpha=3,  \theta=0.24 0.84 6.11 0.27
 \alpha=4,  \theta=0.16 2.36 6.12 0.28
 \alpha=5,  \theta=0.12 3.71 6.19 0.30
 \alpha=6,  \theta=0.10 5.05 6.16 0.32
 \alpha=7,  \theta=0.08 6.22 6.23 0.33
 \alpha=8,  \theta=0.06 7.41 6.18 0.35
 \alpha=9,  \theta=0.05 8.44 6.24 0.37
 \alpha=10,  \theta=0.04 9.54 6.11 0.39

Note: This table reports historical data and model-implied moments of financial variables for various assets. All statistics are annualized and in percent terms. The financial variables are the riskfree rate,  R^{f} , and the excess return of equity over the riskfree rate,  R^{ep}. The moments are mean,  E , and standard deviation,  \sigma . The historical data is from Mehra and Prescott (1985) and covers the 1889-1985 period. Model-implied moments are from the Happiness Maintenance model for various values of hedonic risk aversion,  a_{t} .

Parameter values:  \beta=0.99,  n=2,  \mu=0.018,  \delta=0.036,  \pi=0.43.

Table 4 - Cyclicality and Correlations

  US data No Happiness:

 \theta_{t}=\theta_{t+1}=0

HM-1:
 n=2
HM-2:
 n=5
 P_{t}/D_{t} p-cyclical -0.15 0.08 0.09
 \rho\left( P_{t}/D_{t},P_{t-1}/D_{t-1}\right) 0.78 -0.15 0.55 0.63
 \rho\left( P_{t}/D_{t},P_{t-2}/D_{t-2}\right) 0.59 0.01 0.33 0.54
 \rho\left( P_{t}/D_{t},P_{t-3}/D_{t-3}\right) 0.54 0.00 -0.04 0.43
 \rho\left( P_{t}/D_{t},P_{t-5}/D_{t-5}\right) 0.36 0.00 0.00 0.21

Note: This table reports historical data and model-implied moments of financial variables for various assets. All statistics are annualized and in percent terms. The financial variables are the price to dividend ratios,  P/D, and its lags up to 5 years . The moments are correlations,  \rho . The historical data is from Campbell (1999) and covers the 1889-1985 period. The only difference among columns "No Happiness," "HM-1," and "HM-2" is the calibration of the hedonic risk aversion parameter,  \theta_{t}, under which the happiness maintenance model is solved. The parameter is set equal to zero in column "No Happiness" and as in the benchmark parametrization (specification % latex2html id marker 6765 $ \left( \ref{happy}\right) $ in the text) for columns "HM-1" and "HM-2" with 2 and 5 lags, respectively.

Parameter values:  \alpha=3,  \mu=0.018,  \delta=0.036,  \pi=0.43.

Table 5 - Long-horizon volatility

  US Data No Happiness:

 \theta_{t}=\theta_{t+1}=0

HM-1:
 n=2
HM-2:
 n=5
 \beta_{5} 1.14 1.0 4.9 2.0
 \beta_{10} 1.5 1.0 4.5 2.0
 \beta_{20} 1.61 1.0 3.9 1.7
 \beta_{40} 1.42 1.0 2.8 1.4
 R_{5}^{2} 60% 98% 61% 80%
 R_{10}^{2} 76% 98% 52% 80%
 R_{20}^{2} 70% 98% 40% 75%
 R_{40}^{2} 61% 98% 36% 75%

Note: This table reports regression results of the change in (log) prices,  p_{t}-p_{t-k}, on a constant and the change in (log) consumption,  c_{t}-c_{t-k}, for  k=5,10,20,40 years using historical and model-implied data. The reported statistics are the estimated slope coefficient,  \beta, and  R^{2} of these regressions. The "US data" column runs regressions with annual NYSE data for the 1889-1985 period. The only difference among columns "No Happiness," "HM-1," and "HM-2" is that the regressions are run on model-generated data under alternative calibrations of the hedonic risk aversion parameter,  \theta_{t} . The parameter is set equal to zero in column "No Happiness," and as in the benchmark parametrization (specification % latex2html id marker 6854 $ \left( \ref{happy}\right) $ in the text) for columns "HM-1" and "HM-2" with 2 and 5 lags, respectively.

Parameter values:  \beta=0.99,  \alpha=2,  \theta=0.24,  \mu=0.018,  \delta=0.036,  \pi=0.43.

Table 6 - Long-horizon predictability

  US data No Happiness:  \theta_{t}=\theta_{t+1}=0 HM-1:  n=2 HM-2:  n=5
 \beta_{1} -1.5 -15.6 -6.9 -5.2
 \beta_{2} -3.0 -15.6 -10.8 -6.5
 \beta_{3} -3.7 -15.7 -10.2 -7.7
 \beta_{5} -6.6 -15.1 -10.4 -11.1
 \beta_{10} -12.1 -14.7 -10.2 -10.5
 R_{1}^{2} 4% 7% 28% 13%
 R_{2}^{2} 8% 5% 44% 15%
 R_{3}^{2} 10% 4% 41% 18%
 R_{5}^{2} 19% 3% 42% 25%
 R_{10}^{2} 39% 2% 40% 21%

Note: This table reports regression results of log stock returns,  \sum_{k=1}^{n}r_{t}, on a constant and the log price-dividend ratio for  n=1,2,3,5,10 years using historical and model-implied data. The reported statistics are the estimated slope coefficient,  \beta, and  R^{2} of these regressions. The "US data" column runs regressions with annual NYSE data for the 1889-1985 period. The only difference among columns "No Happiness," "HM-1," and "HM-2" is that the regressions are run on model-generated data under alternative calibrations of the hedonic risk aversion parameter,  \theta_{t} . The parameter is set equal to zero in column "No Happiness," and as in the benchmark parametrization (specification % latex2html id marker 6959 $ \left( \ref{happy}\right) $ in the text) for columns "HM-1" and "HM-2" with 2 and 5 lags, respectively.

Parameter values:  \beta=0.99,  \alpha=2,  \theta=0.24,  \mu=0.018,  \delta=0.036,  \pi=0.43.

Table 7 - Summary of unconditional first and second moments of returns under alternative specifications of the happiness demand process

  HM:

(  \theta=0.24,n=2)

Countercyclical:

(  \theta=0.24,n=2)

HM-1:

(  \theta_{h}=0.25>\theta_{l}=0.23)

 E\left( R^{f}\right) 0.84 3.85 0.84
 E\left( R^{e}\right) 6.95 5.41 6.95
 E\left( R^{ep}\right) 6.11 1.55 6.11
 \sigma\left( R^{f}\right) 5.55 2.89 5.55
 \sigma\left( R^{e}\right) 23.17 13.84 23.17
 \sigma\left( R^{ep}\right) 22.57 13.50 22.57
 \frac{E\left( R^{ep}\right) }{\sigma\left( R^{ep}\right) } 0.27 0.11 0.27

Note: This table reports model-implied moments of financial variables for various assets. All statistics are annualized and in percent terms. The financial variables are the riskfree rate,  R^{f} , the equity return,  R^{e}, the excess return of equity over the riskfree rate,  R^{ep} , and the price to dividend ratio,  P/D. The moments are mean,  E , and standard deviation,  \sigma . The difference between columns "HM," "Countercyclical," and "HM-1" is in the calibration of the hedonic risk aversion parameter,  \theta_{t}, under which the happiness maintenance model is solved. The parameter is set as in the standard parametrization (specification % latex2html id marker 7039 $ \left( \ref{happy}\right) $ in the text) for column "HM," as perfectly negatively correlated with consumption growth for column "Countercyclical," and as a two-state Markov-process that takes values 0.25 and 0.23 in expansions and recessions, respectively.

Parameter values:  \alpha=3,  \mu=0.018,  \delta=0.036,  \pi=0.43.


Figure 1 - Hansen-Jagannathan Bounds

Figure 1: Hansen-Jagannathan Bounds. Four Panels. The figure plots Hansen and Jagannathan (1991)'s bounds and the model implied market price of risk for different values hedonic risk aversion. The market price of risk is the ratio of conditional standard deviation to mean of the model implied pricing kernel. X axis displays the conditional mean, Y axis displays conditional standard deviation. Panels B-C show that low and moderately procyclical hedonic risk aversion brings the equilibrium pricing kernel well within its empirically plausible (Hansen-Jagannathan) bounds. In sharp contrast to this result, Panel A shows that, even with a risk aversion of 10, the market price of risk implied by power utility falls short from satisfying the bounds

Note: The Figure plots Hansen and Jagannathan (1991)'s bounds and the model implied market price of risk for different values hedonic risk aversion. The market price of risk is the ratio of conditional standard deviation to mean of the model implied pricing kernel. X axis displays the conditional mean, Y axis displays conditional standard deviation.



Footnotes

* Federal Reserve Board - Division of Research and Statistics, Washington DC. Phone: (202) 452-2861. Email: [email protected]. This paper is a revised version of Chapter 2 of my Ph.D. dissertation at Columbia University. John Donaldson provided much needed encouragement and guidance and invaluably contributed to deepening my understanding and clarifying the exposition of the concepts presented in the paper. I also acknowledge the advice and support of Thomas Cooley, Tano Santos, and Paolo Siconolfi. I thank Yacine Ait-Sahalia, Gurdip Bakshi, Alberto Bisin, Andrew Caplin, George Constantinides, Jon Elster, Ido Erev, John Geanakoplos, Gur Huberman, Dalida Kadyrzhanova, Rajnish Mehra, Janet Metcalfe, Edmund Phelps, Steven Zeldes; participants at the 2004 Midwest Finance Association Meeting and the "Equity Premium" Conference (University of Exeter); and seminar participants at Columbia University, and the University of Montreal (HEC) for helpful comments. All remaining errors are mine. The views expressed in the paper do not necessarily reflect the views of the Federal Reserve Board or its staff. Return to Text
1. Pigou (1947) elaborated on the notion of amenity utility provided by wealth, in the form of power, sense of security, and control from having resources. Carroll (2000) shows a model with direct utility from wealth might help to explain the high saving rates of the rich. Zou (1994) and Bakshi and Chen (1996) study preferences based on an interpretation of Max Weber's spirit of capitalism as the pursuit of wealth for its own sake. The loss aversion motive studied in Barberis, Huang and Santos (2001) is yet another instance of preferences that depend on changes in financial wealth. Return to Text
2.  a_{t} is more precisely the local curvature of the utility function with respect to wealth, i.e.  -\frac{u_{ww}}{u_{w}}w_{t}. With a slight abuse of terminology we refer to it as "hedonic risk aversion." Return to Text
3. See Appendix A for details. Return to Text
4. The transversality condition is that  E_{0}\sum _{t=0}^{\infty}\beta^{t}u\left( g_{t}\right) <\infty or, equivalently,  \beta\left( 1+\lambda\right) ^{1-\alpha}k<1, where  \lambda is the expected growth rate of output and  k>1. Clearly, since  \lambda>0,  \alpha>1 guarantees that the inequality holds. This argument is analogous to Bakshi and Chen (1996). For a detailed formal development see Kocherlakota (1990). Return to Text
5. For the details on the derivation of the Euler equation see Appendix A. Return to Text
6. Campbell and Cochrane (1999) is perhaps the only habit persistence model that avoids problems with the volatility of the risk-free rate through a clever choice of functional form that enables them to use precautionary saving to counterbalance the strong counter-cyclical variation in risk aversion. Return to Text
7. Details on the remaining part of the computation are given in Appendix A. Return to Text
8. The fortran codes to solve and simulate the model are available upon request from the author. Return to Text
9. The results for the iid case are available upon request. Return to Text
10. Appendix A contains a detailed derivation. Return to Text
11. The latter bet on average only about half chip! Return to Text

This version is optimized for use by screen readers. Descriptions for all mathematical expressions are provided in LaTex format. A printable pdf version is available. Return to Text